Posted: February 26th, 2023

PD5

QUESTION IN THE ATTACHMENT

PADM 530

Article Review Assignment

Instructions

Overview

You will write two article reviews based on the designated articles located in the Learn folder as assigned. You will assess values and conflicts of interest that emerge during the economic development process. Each article review will summarize and critique the author’s position/conclusion in at least 500 words in APA format.

Instructions

Each paragraph of your review should be written using clear and concise language, and thoroughly discuss important details of the article along with the key elements which relate back to concepts within the course.

· Length of assignment: 500 Words

· Format of assignment: APA Style

· Number of citations: No less than 3

· Acceptable sources: Scholarly articles published within the last five years

Note: Your assignment will be checked for originality via the Turnitin plagiarism tool.

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rrse

2

0

Review of Social Economy

ISSN: 00

3

4

6

7

64 (Print)

14

70-

11

62 (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rrse

20

Is Social Capital Really Capital?

Lindon J. Robison , A. Allan Schmid & Marcelo E. Siles

To cite this article: Lindon J. Robison , A. Allan Schmid & Marcelo E. Siles (2002) Is Social Capital
Really Capital?, Review of Social Economy, 60:1, 1-

21

, DOI:

10

.10

8

0/00346760110

12

7074

To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/00346760110127074

Published online: 0

5

Nov 2010.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 2

9

87

View related articles

Citing articles: 31 View citing articles

https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rrse20

https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rrse20

https://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/00346760110127074

https://doi.org/10.1080/00346760110127074

https://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=rrse20&show=instructions

https://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=rrse20&show=instructions

https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/00346760110127074

https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/00346760110127074

https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/citedby/10.1080/00346760110127074#tabModule

https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/citedby/10.1080/00346760110127074#tabModule

Is Social Capital Really Capital?

Lindon J. Robison, A. Allan Schmid and Marcelo E. Siles
Michigan State University

Abstract Social capital has emerged as a paradigm capable of bridging across
various social science disciplines. However, its adoption by social scientists from
different disciplines has led to multiple and often con� icting de� nitions. Besides
con� icting de� nitions, some social scientists have argued that social capital lacks
the properties of capital and should be called something other than capital. This
paper resolves many of the problems created by con� icting de� nitions by pointing
out that the differences have arisen primarily because scientists have included in
the de� nition expressions of its possible uses, where it resides, and how its service
capacity can be changed. This paper argues that these applications of social capital
should not be included in its de� nition. This paper also defends the social capital
paradigm against the claim that it lacks capital-like properties by pointing out that
social capital, when de� ned as sympathy, has many important capital-like
properties including transformation capacity, durability, � exibility, substitutability,
opportunities for decay (maintenance), reliability, ability to create other capital
forms, and investment (disinvestment) opportunities. Finally, this paper compares
social capital to other forms of capital including cultural capital and human
capital.

Keywords: sympathy, social capital, cultural capital, organizational capital,
human capital, physical/� nancial capital, transformation capacity, durability,
� exibility, substitutability, decay (maintenance), reliability, investment
(disinvestment)

INTRODUCTION
The term social capital has taken on so many meanings and enlisted to � ght so
many battles that it is at risk of becoming the ether that � lls the universe.
Commenting on the need to re� ne the de� nition of the term social capital, Castle
wrote: “Unless the social capital concept is used with some degree of precision
and in a comparable manner, it will come to have little value as an analytical
construct.” In what follows, we suggest that social capital’s alternative
de� nitions lack precision because they have included expressions of its possible

REVIEW OF SOCIAL ECONOMY, VOL. LX, NO. 1, MARCH 2002

Review of Social Economy
ISSN 0034 6764 print/ISSN 1470–1

16

2 online © 2002 The Association for Social Economics

http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals
DOI: 10.1080/00346760110127074

uses, where it resides, and how its service capacity can be changed. We
recommend that the de� nition be limited to what social capital is. Then, in the
main part of this paper, we defend the term “social capital” as appropriate and
useful to describe resources associated with interpersonal relationships involving
sympathy because these relationships can claim nearly all of the properties
commonly associated with other forms of capital. Other forms of social capital
not linked to sympathetic relationships, while equally important, are not
illuminated as well by the capital metaphor.

We can enhance communication and cooperative research across academic
disciplines by limiting the de� nition of social capital. Within a particular
discipline, scientists may want to focus on social capital’s applications,
residence, or (dis)investment possibilities unique to their � eld of study.
However, these discussions unique to a � eld of study should not be confused
with the de� nition of social capital, a statement of the form A equals (is) B.

It is our hope that a properly limited social capital de� nition will save social
capital from battles it should not � ght and uniforms it should not wear. The
capital metaphor should be taken seriously. If what economists have learned
about capital is to be useful in new applications, then its use must be limited to
those social relationships that are most capital-like in character.

DIMENSIONS AND DEFINITIONS

While there is some commonality in the meaning given to social capital in the
literature, there are considerable and confusing differences. Perhaps one reason
that researchers have not generally agreed on a de� nition of social capital is that
the de� nitions are not limited to answering the question: what is social capital?
Past de� nitions have included answers to such questions as: where does social
capital reside? How can social capital be used? And how can social capital be
changed? For example, one de� nition of social capital is: “. . . the expectations
for action within a collectivity that affect the economic goals and goal-seeking
behavior of its members, even if these expectations are not oriented toward the
economic sphere” (Portes and Sensenbrenner

19

93). This de� nition appears to
combine what social capital is (the expectations for action within a collectivity)
with what social capital can be used to achieve (affect the economic goals and
goal-seeking behavior of its members).

Coleman (1990) de� ned social capital as a variety of different entities having
two characteristics in common; namely, some aspect of social structure and
ability to facilitate certain actions of individuals who are within the structure.
These entities include obligations, expectations, trust, and information � ows.

REVIEW OF SOCIAL ECONOMY

2

This de� nition, like the one suggested by Portes and Sensenbrenner (1993),
combines what social capital is (a variety of structures) with what social capital
can be used to achieve (facilitate certain actions of individual members of the
group where the group is de� ned by some aspect of social structure). Coleman
(1990) assumes a rational actor calculating individual advantage.

Narayan and Pritchett (1997: 3) de� ne “capital” as something accumulated
which contributes to higher income or better outcomes. The “something” is only
described as horizontal connections and linkages without further de� nition.
Then, they describe � ve processes in which social capital changes outcomes for
the better by facilitating greater cooperation (what it does).

Narayan and Pritchett argue � rst, that increased social capital improves
governments. Second, increased social capital leads to increased community
cooperative action and solves local “common property” problems. Heller (1996)
provides a speci� c example of how horizontal solidarity contributed to the
economic development of the state of Kerala in India. Third, increased social
capital strengthens linkages among individuals that speeds the diffusion of
innovations. Fourth, increased social capital improves the quantity and quality of
information � ows and reduces transactions costs. Finally, increased social
capital pools risks and allows households to pursue more risky and higher return
activities. Narayan and Pritchett’s list is a helpful discussion of the possible
bene� ts that may accrue from increased social capital. They do not, however,
associate with social capital the essential properties of capital as de� ned by
economists. Likewise, Heller speaks of the high density of civic organizations,
vigor of associational life and communal and caste organizations, but little of
what motivates them.

Burt (1992: 9) de� ned social capital as: friends, colleagues, and more general
contacts through whom you receive opportunities to use other forms of capital.
This de� nition of social capital combines a statement of where social capital
resides (with friends, colleagues, and more general contacts) with what it can be
used to accomplish (receive opportunities to use other forms of capital).

Another example of a de� nition that combines a statement of what social
capital is with where it resides is Portes (1995: 12). He de� ned social capital as
the capacity of individuals to command scarce resources by virtue of their
membership in networks or broader social structures. This de� nition can be
separated into a statement of what social capital is (the capacity of individuals
to command scarce resources) with a statement of where social capital resides
(networks or broader social structures).

Sometimes a de� nition of social capital combines statements about what
gives rise to social capital with what social capital can be used to achieve. For

IS SOCIAL CAPITAL REALLY CAPITAL?

3

example, Putnam (1993) de� nes social capital as features of social organizations
such as trust, norms, and networks that can improve the ef� ciency of society by
facilitating coordinated actions. In this de� nition, the basis for social capital
(trust and norms) can be separated from statements of what social capital can do
(improve the ef� ciency of society by facilitating coordinated actions) and where
social capital resides (networks).

Woolcock (1998:

18

) investigates social capital within the context of
economic development policy. He suggests that bottom-up development
depends on intra-community ties labeled “integration” and extra-community
networks labeled “linkages.” Top-down development involves state-society
relations labeled “synergy” and institutional coherence, competence, and
capacity are called “organizational integrity.” The latter is related to what others
call organizational capital. This conception involves a mixture of what capital is
and where it resides. How the content of ties and networks and other institutions
is illuminated by the capital metaphor is not elaborated. All understandings
which coordinate action in a particular way are not capital even if they are
“productive” in the broad sense of the word. Social scientists do not need
another word for all institutions that further economic and social development,
especially if that word implies characteristics of capital that not all institutions
have.

Once social capital is deconstructed into what it is, where it resides, what it
produces (how used) and how produced, it can be seen that “what it is” is
conceptually weak. Can it be clari� ed by reference to capital goods? Consider a
de� nition of capital generally accepted by economists. Capital is: “. . . a
commodity itself used in the production of other goods and services. It is a
human-made input, such as plant or equipment, created to permit increased
production in the future” (Smithson 1982: 111). Capital in this sense represents
an accumulation of foregone consumption, an amount saved for later use. The
capital metaphor has been extended to human capital, organizational capital, and
cultural capital. Human capital has many of the same properties as physical
capital. Fundamentally, human capital emphasizes a surplus value and repre-
sents an investment in education and skills that resides in individuals (Schultz
1961, Becker 1964). Human capital is not destroyed by use and when combined
with other capital goods, it transforms inputs into outputs.

One important difference between social capital and some other forms of
capital is that social capital exists in a social relationship. In contrast, human
capital can reside in the individual alone. This is not to say that human capital
creation is not collective. Even physical capital is in large part a collective
phenomena as Veblen (1908) emphasized. It is created in such institutionalized

REVIEW OF SOCIAL ECONOMY

4

collectivities as corporations, universities, governments, and informal associa-
tions of people wherein knowledge and visions are formed and transferred
(O’Hara 1998).

Organizational capital is described in terms of where it resides: “organiza-
tional relationships, particular members of organizations, the organization’s
repositories of information, or some combination of the above (Tomer 1999:
1049).” Organizational capital can be combined and “embodied in workers in
the form of attitudes and knowledge created through the socialization
processes.”

Cultural capital includes “language and linguistic style, values, de� nitions of
basic knowledge and assumptions . . .” (de Bruin 1998: 169). Cultural capital
can be combined with human capital. “Embodied cultural capital can be
understood as the ability, talent, style, or even speech patterns of people in a
group.” These characteristics are acquired “through the socialization process and
tend to be the marks that distinguish one group from another (de Bruin).”

Obligation, trust, information � ows, organization, friends, membership,
culture, norms, networks, and civic engagement constitute a mixed bag that is
only partially sorted out by distinguishing what social capital is, does, and where
it resides. If the capital goods metaphor is to be useful to analyze social
relationships, it must take seriously the transformative ability of capital to turn
one thing into another. What is it about social relationships that functions as a
factory and puts things in motion? Economists have primarily focused on the
motive of individual utility maximization (greed, for short). If people trust each
other, honor obligations, follow norms, and befriend others only to maximize
their own utility, then these things are just additional commodities to be
exchanged.

If economics is to be broadened to work with other disciplines, other motives
must be acknowledged, such as sympathy and caring. The literature has been
vague about what social capital is. It speaks of ties and linkages which are
suggestive, but imprecise. A “tie” could be two people having each other’s
phone number or being in love. Just what is doing the transforming surely makes
a difference to what happens next. Sympathy sets in motion one-way goods
movements which are not necessarily calculated with the expectation of a return.
Sociologists and psychologists emphasize that much behavior following norms
and obligations is not strictly calculated, but is learned in socialization and
partly unconscious reinforcement. Interacting individuals shape and are shaped
by these cultural processes.

A de� nition of social capital consistent with the Smithson de� nition
generally accepted by economists would substitute for “commodity” the word

IS SOCIAL CAPITAL REALLY CAPITAL?

5

sympathy.1 It would emphasize motive as the foundation of what social capital
is.

Social capital is a person’s or group’s sympathy toward another person or group
that may produce a potential bene� t, advantage, and preferential treatment for
another person or group of persons beyond that expected in an exchange
relationship.

This de� nition separates what it is (sympathy) from what it does (potential
bene� t) and focuses on the transformative capacity of capital residing (em-
bodied) in human relationships. What it is constitutes a motive that differs from
greed. Adam Smith, who wrote The Wealth of Nations, foreshadowed the
concept of social capital when he employed sympathy to differentiate social
preferences. Smith (1976: 219) wrote:

Every man feels his own pleasures and his own pains more sensibly than those of
other people . . . After himself, the members of his own family, those who usually
live in the same house with him, his parents, his children, his brothers and sisters,
are naturally the objects of his warmest affection.

Social capital involves a social relationship of a provider and a recipient. The
provider of sympathy may be (1) an individual; (2) all members of a category
such as an age, gender, racial, or alumni group acting individually on the basis
of social custom and not necessarily aware that others are doing the same; or (3)
it may be generated explicitly by the conscious interaction of people in an
organization. The following are examples of each: (1) a mother is sympathetic
and gives preferential treatment to her child; (2) graduates of a certain school are
sympathetic toward all other grads of the same school and give them preferential
treatment; and (3) a number of people feel sympathy for starving children and
contribute to a scholarship fund administered by a foundation for the bene� t of
quali� ed applicants, or church members are sympathetic to all human kind and
make a Christmas offering and the church board decides on the recipients.

Likewise, the recipient (object of the sympathy) may be (1) an individual
(e.g., a child); (2) all or some members of a categorical group (e.g., graduates);
or (3) some categorical group may be the ultimate recipient, but the intervening
recipient may be an organization which in turn has a process for deciding which
particular individuals qualify for the offered bene� ts. A collective decision may
be required by the recipients to apply for or accept the bene� ts of others’
sympathy. In the latter case, an organization provides the link between

1 Sympathy as used here is consistent with the de� nition found in Webster’s Ninth Collegiate
Dictionary; namely, sympathy is an af� nity, association, or relationship between persons or things
wherein whatever affects one similarly affects the other.

REVIEW OF SOCIAL ECONOMY

6

individual sympathetic donors and individual recipients. In the mind of the
provider, the organization may constitute a symbolized representation of the
ultimate recipients (e.g., Boys Town or CARE). In the latter case, the hungry
child has social capital from their relationship to sympathetic donors (who may
not be known to the child), and CARE is only the administrative conduit for
preferential treatment.

THE CAPITAL METAPHOR

Economists use the word capital in two quite different ways. They speak of
� nancial capital and capital goods as in the Smithson de� nition above. Financial
capital is the symbols and rights associated with credit and money. For example,
when a person receives a loan from a bank, money is created which gives the
recipient the power to direct real resources. In this regard, � nancial capital is a
social relationship and functions as any other institutions to structure opportun-
ities. In this sense, any of the varieties of social, organizational, and cultural
capital are similar to � nancial capital. But, if our purpose is to say that all the
social sciences are interested in human relationships, i.e., institutions, we don’t
need the new word “social capital.” So, in what follows, we shall limit ourselves
to exploring the usefulness of the capital goods concept.

Not everyone accepts the metaphor of capital goods to describe relationships
of sympathy that may produce potential bene� ts.2 Re� ecting on a social capital
workshop sponsored by the World Bank, economist and Nobel laureate Kenneth
Arrow (1999) urged abandonment of the metaphor of capital and the term
“social capital.” He emphasized that the term “capital” implied a deliberate
sacri� ce in the present for future bene� ts that he claimed was inappropriate to
describe social networks organized for reasons other than economic value for
the participants. As will be seen below, however, social capital may indeed
involve a saving and investment today to obtain future bene� ts and Arrow’s
objection seems misplaced.

In the same World Bank conference described earlier, Robert Solow (1999)
criticized social capital as an attempt to gain conviction from a bad analogy. He
argued that “capital” stands for a stock of produced or natural factors of
production that can be expected to yield productive services for some time.

2 Woolcock (1998) has identi� ed several other names for a concept similar to social capital
including “intangible assets” (Veblen 1908); “social energy” (Hirschman 1958); “social capability”
(Ohkawa and Rosovsky 1973); “sociability” (Hirschman); and “moral resources” (Hirschman), to
name a few. See also Durlauf (1999).

IS SOCIAL CAPITAL REALLY CAPITAL?

7

Baron and Hannon (1994) raise another objection to the metaphor of social
capital. They argue that to qualify as “capital”’ an entity must possess an
opportunity cost, something that social capital lacks. Woolcock (1998:46)
responded to this objection: “. . . much of one’s social capital stems from an
inherited endowment over which one has little in� uence—but it is also the case
that people can and do make deliberate, hence costly, efforts to increase their
social capital . . .” The point can be illustrated by a homely example. Imagine a
person who has been spending each day harvesting apples by hand. Apples are
the person’s only food supply. To have time to build an apple picking machine,
the person must save by eating fewer of the harvested apples today in order to
eat tomorrow while creating the capital good. Similarly, the person can eat fewer
apples today in order to give them to a friend and thus create a stock of social
capital that is capable of producing emotional and physical goods in the future.
Foregone consumption today creates capital for tomorrow.

The social capital metaphor may suffer because economists and sociologists
typically use the term “capital” in slightly different ways. Quoting again from
Castle (1998: 625): “Capital in any form quali� es as capital only if it makes
humans more productive when they use it in combination with other forms of
capital. Sociologists may refer to social capital as ‘bad’ or ‘good’ depending on
whether it is useful to humans in a given context. The economist probably would
not refer to a ‘bad’ social arrangement as social capital, although it might qualify
as an economic institution.” In this regard, requiring capital to be used for
productive compared to destructive purposes is not helpful. Most productive
processes involving capital produce both goods and bads. A plant may produce
steel (a good) and smoke (a bad). Would you say the plant is not capital because
it produces smoke along with steel?

Regardless of whether one agrees or disagrees with the objections to the
metaphor of capital and the term social capital, Arrow’s recommendation that
the term social capital be abandoned comes too late. The calves are out of the
barn and into green pastures and not likely to return soon. The term social
capital is now � rmly entrenched in the language of social scientists. Thus, for
now and for some considerable time in the future, the term “social capital” will
be in common use among most social scientists, if not most economists, and the
task will be to make the most of it.

CAPITAL-LIKE PROPERTIES OF SOCIAL CAPITAL

With the term social capital � rmly entrenched in the social sciences, it may be
appropriate to ask: what does social capital or sympathetic relationships have in
common with capital goods? To answer this question: “is social capital really

REVIEW OF SOCIAL ECONOMY

8

capital?” several properties of capital are examined next and compared with
properties of social capital as de� ned earlier in this paper.

The essential properties of physical capital goods are: transformation
capacity, durability, � exibility, substitutability, decay, reliability, ability to
create one capital form from another, opportunities for (dis)investment, and
alienability. In what follows, we intend to point out that social capital, as de� ned
in this paper, shares all of these essential capital-like properties.

Transformation Capacity

Transformation capacity relates to the essential characteristics of capital goods;
i.e., goods to make goods by transforming inputs into outputs and is itself not
necessarily transformed. Capital goods, like factories and machines, transform
raw material inputs into other forms including both consumption goods or
additional capital goods. Of course, a capital good’s service potential depends
on the presence of other inputs. Examples of physical capital include heating
plants with their potential to produce heat from coal; cars, buses, and planes
with their potential to provide travel services; surgical equipment with its
potential to supply medical services; and housing with its potential to provide
shelter services. This conceptual separation of capital from its service � ows and
other resources required in the transformation processes allows us to ask what
are the processes that transform the inputs into outputs, and how do capital and
nondurable inputs substitute and complement each other in the production of
services and goods? These are the questions and perspective provided by apt use
of the capital metaphor.

Social capital, like other forms of capital, requires not only sympathetic
relationships but other inputs to provide preferential treatment and bene� ts.
Social capital can be combined with other inputs to provide services that meet
human needs in four essential areas of human experience: economic services,
social services, validation services, and information services. A description of
human needs and the importance of relationships in meeting these needs is a
subject for long discussions. The main point emphasized here is that human
relationships are required to meet our most basic emotional needs. Human
relationships can be prized in themselves and directly utilized much as a
refrigerator or other durable good are used by a consumer. Or, relationships can
be used to produce other goods much as a machine is used to produce consumer
goods. Thus, the services can be both immediate and in the future. Consider the
following four service categories supplied by social capital.

(1) Economic services provided directly by social capital are distinguished
from economic services motivated by sel� sh preferences. Social capital that

IS SOCIAL CAPITAL REALLY CAPITAL?

9

meets economic needs requires feelings of caring or sympathy that transform
and vicariously link the consumption of one person to the utility of another.
Obligation, norms, and rule following cannot do this. (2) The social needs to
experience caring and regard from others and for others is at the root of human
nature and requires sympathetic personal relationships. Again, obligation and
norm following cannot produce this good. (3) The need to be validated is also
a foundation need that is ful� lled through interpersonal experience. Only
communication from those you respect and who respect you can provide
supportive feedback to one’s self-image. Apparently similar feedback seen as
motivated by obligation and habit or ingratiation with expectation of future
favors does not provide the same transformation. (4) Finally, there is the need to
see yourself through the eyes of others and to receive encouragement, moral
support, and acceptance.

It is sympathetic relationships that have capital’s transformative potential to
provide economic, social, validation, and re� ective services. This capacity is its
main characteristic that identi� es it as a form of capital. The capital metaphor
provides less insight to understanding the role of other kinds of social
relationships. This is not to say that other forms are less important, just that the
capital metaphor is less useful there.

Durability

Durability associated with physical capital refers to capital’s ability to retain its
identity after and during the process of providing services. A tractor, after
delivering pulling services, is still recognized as a tractor with potential to pull
and provide transportation. A cow, after producing offspring and milk, is still
recognized as a cow with milk and offspring producing potential. In contrast to
durables are expendables that lose their identity during their provision of
services. For example, seed and fuel are most of the time considered
expendables because while providing growing and energy services, they lose
their identity. Seeds become plants and fuel becomes energy and neither
expendable is recognized for what it was before it provided services.

Social capital possesses different degrees of durability. There may be weak
af� nity ties capable of producing only a limited amount of services before
disintegrating. A causal friend may be willing to provide free transportation a
few times but then later be unresponsive to requests. Some forms of social
capital are durable almost to the point of being indestructible. These extremely
durable forms of social capital are often associated with family connections that
remain unchanged even when repeated service extractions are made. (How

REVIEW OF SOCIAL ECONOMY

10

many dinner and laundry services can children expect before further services are
refused by their parents?)

Capital whose service potential is nearly indestructible is called endurables.
Endurables are little affected by time or use. A � ne jeweled watch may keep
time for generations. Land, for example, has its service potential nearly
unaffected by reasonable use. So it is with social capital. Social capital that
resides in family members may be nearly indestructible, an endurable, while
social capital embedded with friends with whom you attend sporting events may
be of limited durability and needs continual maintenance.

How does the capital goods attribute of durability facilitate analysis of social
capital? It focuses attention on making continuous use of such capital; e.g., keep
the factory going night and day. It calls attention to the possibility of economies
of scale (volume) once the initial investment is made. It suggests that the return
to a relatively expensive durable be compared to a cheaper, but expendable,
form of social capital.

Flexibility

Flexibility refers to the range and number of services available from a capital
source. Some capital forms are designed for a speci� c use and not applicable to
others. In this category, one might think of a specialized medical instrument
used to remove cataracts. Or, one might think of keys that only work in one
lock. Capital forms whose services can only be used to meet highly specialized
needs are called in� exible capital forms. In contrast to in� exible capital forms
are � exible capital forms whose services can be used to provide a wide range of
services. For example, electric ranges are used mostly for cooking services, but
in emergencies may be used to provide heating services in the con� ned space in
which they are located. While cars provide transportation services, they can also
be used to pull trailers, carry groceries, and provide shelter from the elements.
Cars not only may be used to produce a wide range of services, but the rate at
which transportation services may be varied often ranges from nearly zero to
120 miles per hour.

Like physical capital, social capital may be either � exible or in� exible. Some
forms of social capital, such as might be available from a sibling, can be used to
obtain a kidney donation, � nancial resources such as loans, transportation,
information, favorable reviews, support for awards, and companionship on
otherwise lonely occasions. One would not expect such a range of services from
the bank teller who greets you by name when you conduct your � nancial
business. The teller might provide some preferential treatment, but these would

IS SOCIAL CAPITAL REALLY CAPITAL?

11

likely be related to the services she or he does in the routine course of her/his
work at the bank.

Substitutes and Complements

The economic way of thinking asks about complements and substitutes. Tractors
provide pulling services in most developed countries, but animals may substitute
for these services in many less developed agricultural settings. Barns and silos
provide storage services, but trees and tents may substitute for these services in
emergencies. Tractors and plows are complements. Each one enhances the
productivity of the other.

Sympathy is a substitute for monitoring. A person who has sympathy for you
will not be opportunistic. Commitment and obligation are also substitutes for
monitoring costs. Worker cooperatives can reduce monitoring costs if self-
determination enables employees to identify with the corporation and then avoid
shirking (Lutz 1997).

Sympathy can substitute for greed and obligation and the several motives are
often mixed in practice. But, greed and obligation are not substitutes for
sympathy in providing validation or creating utility for Alpha from Beta’s
consumption; i.e., in providing emotional services. Sympathy is not expected to
be found alone, but rather in complementary combinations with motives of self-
seeking and ful� lling obligations.

Decay (Maintenance)

Decay (maintenance) refers to the manner in which the service capacity of
durables is reduced (maintained). Physical capital’s service potential decays
mostly through use, the passage of time, and the absence of maintenance. Wear
is a natural feature of nearly all forms of physical capital. One might think of a
barn that provides storage services. The service capacity of the barn is related to
the physical dimension of the facility and the condition of the structure. In this
instance, the barn’s decay depends on the passage of time and the application of
maintenance rather than use, since its decay is unrelated to the number of objects
stored. On the other hand, the increasing number and frequency of engine
revolutions directly alters the potential of many mechanical durables whose
decay depends on use. Finally, some durable’s service capacity varies little with
time or use, like paintings in a museum (if properly maintained), while other
durables, such as paper cups, may have rapid decay functions.

Social capital, like physical capital, is subject to decay from use, the passage
of time, and lack of maintenance. One might develop social capital within a

REVIEW OF SOCIAL ECONOMY

12

neighborhood that provides valuable services. But when a member of the
community moves, at � rst there are efforts to maintain contact, but eventually
the lack of maintenance in the form of face-to-face contacts soon diminishes the
strength of the ties and the potential to extract services. In other cases, in
endurable relationships such as might exist between family members, the
passage of time and the absence of regular face-to-face contacts does very little
to diminish the social capital service potential. Finally, sometimes the too
frequent request for services may exhaust one’s social capital or potential to
receive preferential treatment. On the other hand, some social capital may
require use to be sustained. A friend who is never called on for help may feel
ignored and become less friendly.

Reliability

Reliability concerns the predictability of capital’s service delivery. Will it
perform as expected (as it did previously)? Dependability has two dimensions.
These two dimensions include longevity and intensity. For example, a light bulb
provides lighting services at a particular intensity. Its reliability mostly deals
with its longevity—how often will the light bulb light up? Its wattage intensity,
however, is not generally in question. The longevity of light bulbs is particularly
important for traf� c lights and lights in other sensitive areas.

Professional football players may also be considered to have a form of capital
(human capital). One important quality of a skilled football player is his
intensity in a particular game. A player whose intensity is widely variable is less
valuable than one who continues to provide predictable levels of high
performance each game.

Unpredictability of intensity or duration usually reduces the value of capital.
Moreover, capital forms that are reliable are generally recognized and rewarded
in the marketplace. Diehard batteries and Honda cars are generally recognized
and rewarded for their reliability.

Social capital clearly has a reliability dimension. Some social capital invested
in close friends and family members is highly reliable and its performance
predictable. Other forms of social capital may be situationally dependent. For
example, a person who has achieved some new signi� cant success may become
more sympathetic and more willing to provide preferential treatment than
previously. Sometimes a relationship “gone bad” may unexpectedly end one’s
social capital or make it � uctuate unpredictably. In any case, conversations that
begin by asking: “can we ask Jane or Jon for a favor?” are recognizing that
social capital has a reliability dimension.

IS SOCIAL CAPITAL REALLY CAPITAL?

13

Ability to Create Other Capital

Ability to create other capital forms refers to capital’s ability to be used to create
the same or different kinds of capital. For example, metal presses are used to
create metal products for consumption or to create parts for still other metal
presses or used to create new forms of capital such as a lathe. We recognize,
however, that what is created is distinct from the original capital used in the
creation process. Likewise, social capital can be used to strengthen existing
levels of social capital or be used to create new forms of social capital. For
example, person A might have social capital with person B who introduces him/
her to person C. Then, because of their friendship with B, persons A and C
develop social capital. These persons may be in corporations, education, or
government as well as in families or communities. Sympathy motivates
preferential treatment, which in turn may create more sympathy. Sympathy may
deepen to empathy and caring to loving.

Social capital, like other forms of physical capital, can also be used to
create forms of capital different from itself. For example, at some point in time
publicly elected of� cials approved the Morrill Act that resulted in the creation
of the Land Grant Universities. Those responsible for creating the Land
Grant System were undoubtedly in� uenced in their action by sympathy for
others. However, what they created was something different from social
capital. What they created was an institution with resources, rights, and
responsibilities and the ability to grant preferential treatment to many in-
dividuals. In addition, it became a setting in which much social capital has been
and will be created; e.g., students forming bonds of friendship. Yet, saying that
social capital is embedded in the university would not be correct though its
resources and rules create advantages and disadvantages for individuals. Social
capital continues to reside in networks of individuals, individuals who are
capable of caring and experiencing vicarious sensing of another person’s well-
being. Sympathy makes it easier to accept the property claims of others as
legitimate.

Sometimes sympathetic individuals develop feelings of attachment toward an
object whose signi� cance increases because of social capital among these
individuals. For example, a picture of a friend has special meaning because of
social capital while the picture of someone unknown has little signi� cance. Yet,
we would be careful to say that the picture has attachment value, not social
capital. Some individuals may have special experiences with hospitals, service
groups, and religious or ethnic organizations for which they develop attachment
values. They may endow these with funds or other resources to help them in
their missions. Nevertheless, the hospitals, service groups, and religious or

REVIEW OF SOCIAL ECONOMY

14

ethnic organizations are not endowed with social capital, although the charitable
act may create social capital in some individuals.

A collection of students may initially form because of a common sel� sh
interest in a subject matter leading them to register for the same class. Then,
because of group projects and synergistic group studies, the class members may
develop social capital for each other that may also meet some sociability needs.
Another group may form around a common interest in an activity to meet a
sociability need. For example, one such group may organize to play bridge.
However, this group may strengthen its ties and its social capital by agreeing to
form an investment club. Now their group meets their needs not only for
sociability but also provides a useful activity (investing) that may further their
economic interests (earning returns on their investments). Most service clubs,
such as Rotary or Kiwanis, organize not only to meet their social needs but to
provide service to their communities. It is unlikely that these clubs would
prosper if their only purpose was to advance their social needs.

Investment (Disinvestment) Opportunities

Investment (disinvestment) opportunities refer to one’s ability to create new
capital (or destroy existing capital). Alienation of existing social capital will be
discussed in a separate section below. Investment (disinvestment) opportunities
associated with new physical capital are generally recognized. Inputs of cement
and steel are combined to make a building. Like physical capital formation, one
can invest in getting closer. One can combine inputs like gifts, entertaining, and
communication to produce sympathy by others for you. Social capital is
produced in a similar way that a machine is produced, by combining inputs (in
a production function). The capital metaphor helps to conceptualize this
production process. Social capital is created through acts of service, gifts,
mutually bene� cial interactions, and discovered and created kernels of com-
monalities. Kernels of commonality may be shared traits, qualities, life-styles,
beliefs, and values which often distinguish “us” from “them.”

Is there a contradiction between individual or collective investment in social
capital that implies calculation and the emotive non-calculating response of
persons for persons? Alpha can consciously try to get closer to Beta and acquire
social capital. If A is aware of it and calculates her response, we have the usual
process of exchange. But, if B is unaware of A’s intent (or A is not really
consciously trying to create social capital), there are elements of emotion and
the dynamic is in part unconscious. Social scientists, labor mediators, and
politicians may consciously create an environment in which the emotive
elements are directed in a certain way even if the participants are partly or

IS SOCIAL CAPITAL REALLY CAPITAL?

15

wholly non-calculating in their response. While the source of sympathy may be
emotive and non-calculating, it can lead to calculation of how to be of most use
to the recipient of one’s sympathy.

The investment (disinvestment) processes used to create (destroy) social
capital vary in intensity and durability. The intensity of the social capital
investment depends on the intensity of the human relation experience and is
related to communication. Intense communication would be face-to-face
contacts that occur on a regular basis. Less intense communications are those
that occur periodically through a medium. Communication by phone, mail, e-
mail, and messages passed through a third party illustrate this later form of
communication. The intensity of communication may also depend on the
relationship between those communicating. Face-to-face communication
between strangers is likely less intense than face-to-face communication
between a husband and wife, a priest and penitent, and a parent and child.
Finally, the intensity of social relations may be a function of the purpose for the
communication. When the purpose of the communication is to produce, i.e.,
enhance one’s economic position, validate or be validated, to exchange
information, or to express caring, the intensity of the communication is
different.

Alienability

Existing capital may be transferred from its creator to others by gift, inheritance,
sale, or rental. One may inherit some forms of capital goods such as factories
and houses. Indeed, most families have determined an inheritance plan to pass
on its capital to heirs upon the death of the capital’s owners. Like physical
capital, one may inherit social capital created by one’s family members or
friends. For example, friends of my parents may become my friends because of
the efforts of my parents. A baby is born into a particular social structure and in
particular to a family and may immediately “own” social capital. This capital is
inherited because the parents identify the child as belonging to them. Despite
many service withdrawals, social capital bene� ts accrue to the young child
without any effort. But, as the child ages, he/she must invest to maintain the
social capital.

Physical capital goods can be rented or purchased from their original creators
or subsequent owners. But, since existing social capital is a relationship, it
cannot be transferred by its bene� ciary without the consent of the benefactor(s).
In that sense, it is misleading to speak of owning social capital. Alienation is not
essential to the de� nition of capital or we could not speak of human capital.
Human capital is embodied in a person and cannot be alienated separately from

REVIEW OF SOCIAL ECONOMY

16

the person. I can teach others my skill for a fee, but I cannot transfer it directly
to another by ceasing to use it as in the case of a factory.

In summary, when we say there are different forms of social capital or that
social capital has changed, what do we mean? We mean that some social capital
can be used for economic advantages, some for social ful� llment, some for
validation, and some for information. When we say it has changed, we may
mean that social capital’s service potential, � exibility, ethical use, decay pattern,
reliability, or its ability to create other capital forms has changed.

CULTURAL AND ORGANIZATIONAL CAPITAL

Reference has already been made to the complementarity and partial sub-
stitutability of capital goods, social capital, cultural capital, and organizational
capital. Some further elaboration may be useful. In some cultures, parents teach
their children to return lost objects and always to tell the truth. In addition,
because of the parents’ social capital with their children and the reinforcement
from the community, the children may also adopt the values of returning lost
objects and always telling the truth. Visitors to this culture might � nd this form
of cultural capital particularly helpful in setting up a business and if pressed
could even place a dollar value on the cultural capital to which they have
access.

It is useful to distinguish these learned and internalized behavioral norms
from social capital. A person can return lost objects from a learned sense of
commitment without any (or much) sympathy with the owner. Amartya Sen
(1982) distinguishes sympathy from commitment. The person enmeshed in
cultural capital may not even consider alternative behavior and be little
in� uenced by thoughts of what would happen if the norm were not im-
plemented. (See also Minkler 1999.) Behavior contrary to the norm would
destroy the person’s image of their ideal self. When cultural capital is widely
shared, it increases the opportunities for reinforcement and the generality of
bene� ts or what Fukuyama (1995) calls the “radius of spontaneous
cooperation.”

When groups of individuals form certain cultural norms accepted by the
population, that is they have cultural capital, these may sometimes substitute for
personalized social capital. When a person has access to cultural capital that
gives him/her honest answers and the return of lost objects, the person may not
need to depend on personalized forms of social capital to gain access to reliable
information and lost objects. When these facilitating cultural norms are absent,
individuals may need to depend on more personalized forms of social capital.

IS SOCIAL CAPITAL REALLY CAPITAL?

17

The same honest behavior might also be produced by formal legal institutions
and sanctions. Again, this might be valuable to those contemplating investment
is a business. In addition, the nation-state is not the only source of governance.
Organizations make rules which apply to their members/employees. Some
become learned habits in which case we speak of business culture, and some are
honored because of sanctions within the organization including expulsion.

Cultural capital and organizational capital may also provide the experienced
kernels of commonality essential for the development of social capital.
Agreement on cultural values and norms suggests an absence of con� ict
between persons in a relationship. Beginning with an agreement on cultural
norms and values, cultural capital may provide the opportunities to � nd other
kernels of commonality and develop synergistic activities which increase
sympathy and individual and collective investments in social capital. Class,
gender, and race constitute af� nity groups and kernels of commonality—
sometimes for good and sometimes for disadvantage (Egerton 1997).

The main point here, however, is that social capital can be used to create
more of itself and create still different forms of capital, including cultural and
organizational. In addition, social capital and other forms of capital can
substitute for and complement each other in varying degrees.

CONCLUSIONS

The capital metaphor is not needed to show that institutions make a difference,
and little will be gained by calling all institutions capital. Our purpose in this
essay is not to assert guardianship of the term “social capital.” We have our
preferred de� nition which places social capital within a particular group of
social relationships which are emotive. The main purpose of the essay is to
explore the utility of the capital metaphor by asking if social capital has the
following features of physical capital: transformative capacity, durability,
� exibility, substitutability, decay, reliability, capacity for investment and
disinvestment, and ability to create other forms of capital. The capital metaphor
seems to have the most suggestive power when applied to sympathetic
relationships. This is particularly the case with respect to transformative
capacity—that which puts things into motion. Only sympathy, for example, can
transform one person’s consumption into the utility of another.

We offer several distinctions which may facilitate study of where social
capital comes from and what it does. These include the following: separation of
the source or motive of social capital from its services (what it does) and where
it resides; separation of the motive capacity of sympathy from that of

REVIEW OF SOCIAL ECONOMY

18

commitment (cultural capital and norms) and from formal legal institutions; and
separation of the motive derived from sympathy from the motive of narrow self-
enhancement.

How the capital metaphor is conceptualized will impact empirical measure-
ment. Most surveys, to date, have focused on intermediate or � nal products
rather than on what motivates and drives production. For example, the World
Values Study asks if people trust others or the government. See Knack and
Keefer (1997) and also Sudarsky (1999). There has been little investigation of
where trust comes from. Trust could simply be the result of previous non-
opportunistic behavior by others or it could be based on af� nity. There are
various surveys of membership in organizational and civic participation
(outcomes), but again little attention to the driving force behind participation.
Getting serious about the capital goods metaphor would suggest digging into
motivation behind trust and participation (Schmid 2000).

We close with our preferred de� nition of social capital which calls attention
to a heretofore much neglected motive for behavior:

Social capital is a person’s or group’s sympathy toward another person or group
that may produce a potential bene� t, advantage, and preferential treatment for
another person or group of persons beyond that expected in an exchange
relationship.

REFERENCES

Arrow, K. J. (1999) “Observations on Social Capital,” in P. Dasgupta and I. Serageldin
(eds) Social Capital: A Multifaceted Perspective, Washington: The World Bank:
3–5.

Baron, J. and Hannon, M. (1994) “The Impact of Economics on Contemporary
Sociology,” Journal of Economic Literature 32(3): 1111–1146.

Becker, G. S. [1964] (1993) Human Capital, Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Burt, G. (1992) Structural Holes, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Castle, E. N. (1998) “A Conceptual Framework for the Study of Rural Places,” American

Journal of Agricultural Economics 80(3): 621–631.
Coleman, J. (1988) “Social Capital in the Creation of Human Capital,” American Journal

of Sociology 94: S95–S120.
Coleman, J. (1990) Foundations of Social Theory, Cambridge: Belknap Press/Harvard

University Press.
de Bruin, A. (1998) “Cultural Capital,” in P. O’Hara (ed.) Encyclopedia of Political

Economy, London: Routledge.
Durlauf, S. (1999) “The Case ‘Against’ Social Capital,” Focus, 20(3): 1–5, University of

Wisconsin, Institute for Research on Poverty. Also available at .

IS SOCIAL CAPITAL REALLY CAPITAL?

19

Egerton, M. (1997) “Occupational Inheritance: The Role of Cultural Capital and
Gender,” Work, Employment and Gender 11(2): 263–282.

Fukuyama, F. (1995) Trust, New York: The Free Press.
Heller, P. (1996) “Social Capital as a Product of Class Mobilization and State

Intervention: Industrial Workers in Kerala, India,” World Development 24(6):
1055–1071.

Hirshman, A. (1958) The Strategy of Economic Development, New Haven: Yale
University Press.

Knack, S., and Keefer, P. (1997) “Does Social Capital Have An Economic Payoff? A
Cross-Country Investigation,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 112: 1252–1288.

Lutz, M. (1997) “The Mondragon Co-operative Complex: An Application of Kantian
Ethics to Social Economics,” International Journal of Social Economics 24(12):
1404–1421.

Minkler, L. (1999) “The Problem with Utility,” Review of Social Economy 57:4–24.
Narayan, D. and Pritchett, L. (1997) “Cents and Sociability: Household Income and

Social Capital in Rural Tanzania,” World Bank Research Working Paper No. 1796,
Washington: The World Bank.

O’Hara, P. A. (1998) “Capital and Inequality in Today’s World,” in Doug Brown (ed.)
Thorstein Veblen in the Twenty-First Century, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

Ohkawa, K. and Rosovsky, H. (1973) Japanese Economic Growth: Trend Acceleration in
the Twentieth Century, Stanford: Stanford University Press.

Portes, A. (1995) “Economic Sociology and the Sociology of Immigration: A Conceptual
Overview,” in Alejandro Portes (ed.) The Economic Sociology of Immigration: Essays
on Networks, Ethnicity, and Entrepreneurship, New York: Russell Sage Foundation,
pp. 1–41.

Portes, A. and Sensenbrenner, J. (1993) “Embeddedness and Immigration: Notes on the
Social Determinants of Economic Action,” American Journal of Sociology 98(6):
1320–1350.

Putnam, R. (1993) Making Democracy Work, Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Schmid, A. (2000) “Sources of Social Capital,” Staff Paper No. 00–07, Department of

Agricultural Economics, Michigan State University, East Lansing, MI, April 20.
Schultz, T. (1961) “Investment in Human Capital,” The American Economic Review

51(1): 1–17.
Sen, A. (1982) “Rational Fools: A Critique of the Behavioral Foundations of Economic

Theory,” Ch. 4 in Choice, Welfare and Measurement, Cambridge: MIT Press, pp.
84–106.

Smith, A. (1976) The Theory of Moral Sentiments, edited by D. D. Raphael and A. L.
Mac� e, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Smithson, C. W. (1982) “Capital, A Factor of Production,” in D. Greenwald (ed.)
Encyclopedia of Economics, New York: McGraw-Hill, 111–112.

Solow, R. M. (1999) “Notes on Social Capital and Economic Performance,” in P.
Dasgupta and I. Serageldin (eds.) Social Capital: A Multifaceted Perspective,
Washington: The World Bank: 6–12.

Sudarsky, J. (1999) “Columbia’s Social Capital: The National Measurement with the
Barcus,” .

REVIEW OF SOCIAL ECONOMY

20

Tomer, J. (1999) “Social and Organizational Capital,” in P. O’Hara (ed.) Encyclopedia of
Political Economy, London: Routledge: 1049–1051.

Veblen, T. (1908) “On the Nature of Capital, Intangible Assets and the Pecuniary
Magnate,” Quarterly Journal of Economics 23(1): 104–136.

Woolcock, M. (1998) “Social Capital and Economic Development: Towards A
Theoretical Synthesis and Policy Framework,” Theory and Society 27: 151–208.

IS SOCIAL CAPITAL REALLY CAPITAL?

21

Full Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at
https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rhpd20

Housing Policy Debate

ISSN: 1051-1482 (Print) 2152-050X (Online) Journal homepage: https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rhpd20

The myth of social capital in community
development

James DeFilippis

To cite this article: James DeFilippis (2001) The myth of social capital in community
development, Housing Policy Debate, 12:4, 781-806, DOI: 10.1080/10511482.2001.9521429

To link to this article: https://doi.org/10.1080/10511482.2001.9521429

Published online: 31 Mar 2010.

Submit your article to this journal

Article views: 7586

View related articles

Citing articles: 26 View citing articles

https://www.tandfonline.com/action/journalInformation?journalCode=rhpd20

https://www.tandfonline.com/loi/rhpd20

https://www.tandfonline.com/action/showCitFormats?doi=10.1080/10511482.2001.9521429

https://doi.org/10.1080/10511482.2001.9521429

https://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=rhpd20&show=instructions

https://www.tandfonline.com/action/authorSubmission?journalCode=rhpd20&show=instructions

https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/10511482.2001.9521429

https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/mlt/10.1080/10511482.2001.9521429

https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/citedby/10.1080/10511482.2001.9521429#tabModule

https://www.tandfonline.com/doi/citedby/10.1080/10511482.2001.9521429#tabModule

The Myth of Social Capital
in Community Development

James DeFilippis
King’s College, London

Abstract

This article argues that contemporary interest in social capital by community develop-
ment theorists, funders, and practitioners is misguided and needs to be thoroughly re-
thought. It argues that social capital, as understood by Robert Putnam and people in-
fluenced by his work, is a fundamentally flawed concept because it fails to understand
issues of power in the production of communities and because it is divorced from eco-
nomic capital. Therefore, community development practice based on this understanding
of social capital is, and will continue to be, similarly flawed.

The article further argues that instead of Putnam’s understanding of social capital,
community development practice would be better served by returning to the way the
concept was used by Glenn Loury and Pierre Bourdieu and concludes with a discussion
of how these alternative theories of social capital can be realized in community devel-
opment practice.

Keywords: Development/revitalization; Urban environment

Introduction

The extremely rapid rise of social capital is one of the dominant trends
in American social science and public policy over the past decade, and
this is particularly true of work in housing and community development.
This was obvious at the spring 1999 meeting of the Urban Affairs Asso-
ciation in Louisville, KY. Social capital was the organizing theme of the
conference, and emphasis was placed on how social capital can be gener-
ated in low-income communities in the United States. If the meeting
was any indication, social capital had, in only about half a decade, be-
come one of the principal concerns of community development practi-
tioners and researchers. Shortly thereafter, two students walked into
their high school in the affluent suburb of Littleton, CO, and began
shooting their classmates. This tragic event sparked debates in Ameri-
can public life, among them the issue of the isolation and alienation of
much of suburban life (Hamilton 1999; Schiff 1999).

Of course, this was not a new criticism to be lodged against the suburbs;
people have been making it for quite some time (Friedan 1963; Jackson
1985; Langdon 1994; Wood 1958). But, the feeling of isolation in afflu-
ent suburbs (which are now only a segment of the much more race- and
class-diverse suburban world) took on new strength in the 1990s and

Housing Policy Debate · Volume 12, Issue 4 781
© Fannie Mae Foundation 2001. All Rights Reserved. 781

resulted in, among other things, the rapid growth of both the cohousing
and New Urbanist movements (Hanson 1996; Katz 1994; Knack 1996;
McCamant and Durrett 1988; Muschamp 1996; Talen 1999).

But, this sense of isolation presents a problem. If people who are afflu-
ent in the United States are struggling with social disconnectedness
and isolation, why are people who are concerned with economic develop-
ment in low-income areas emphasizing the importance of social connec-
tions and networks as a way of moving low-income people and commu-
nities out of poverty? There seems, in short, to be disjuncture between,
on the one hand, the experiences of the affluent and, on the other, the
prescriptions for the poor in American life. This disjuncture, in and of
itself, should lead people to question the utility of the social capital
framework in community economic development.

This article will discuss the meanings and uses of social capital and
argue that its recently acquired privileged position in community eco-
nomic development is misguided. To be specific, however, this article is
not an argument that social capital does not matter or that it is not an
important component in the production and reproduction of individual
success and class status. Instead, the argument is that we need to be
very careful about how we define and use the term social capital. Social
capital is an “elastic term” (Moore Lappe and Du Bois 1997, 119), with
a variety of meanings. But the understanding of social capital that has
become incorporated into community development theory and practice
is the social capital of Robert Putnam (1993a, 1993b, 1995, 1996, 1998,
2000), in which the term is both combined with notions of civil society
and assumed to be a principal engine of economic growth and democra-
tic government. Putnam’s arguments, however, are deeply flawed and
have little empirical or theoretical support, so community development
work informed by his framework will be similarly flawed and misguid-
ed. Before making these arguments, however, this article will briefly
discuss the concept of social capital and how it has evolved through its
use by Loury (1977), Bourdieu (1985), Coleman (1988) and then, ulti-
mately, Putnam (1993a, 1993b, 1995, 1996, 2000) and his followers.

What is social capital?1

While time and space constraints do not permit a thorough description
of the enormous literature on social capital that has emerged in the past
seven or so years (Chupp 1999; Fine 2001; Foley and Edwards 1997,
1998; Portes 1998; Wills 2000), it is important to briefly describe the dif-
ferent meanings given to the term. It is unclear who first used the term,
but an important early use came from Loury (1977) in a book chapter

782 James DeFilippis

1 This section borrows heavily from Portes’s presidential address to the American Soci-
ological Association (1998).

that criticized the narrowly individualistic and atomistic understanding
of human capital in neoclassical economic theory. He wrote:

The social context within which individual maturation occurs
strongly conditions what otherwise equally competent individuals
can achieve. This implies that absolute equality of opportunity, where
an individual’s chance to succeed depends only on his or her innate
capabilities, is an ideal that cannot be achieved.…An individual’s
social origin has an obvious and important effect on the amount of
resources that is ultimately invested in his or her development. It
may thus be useful to employ a concept of “social capital” to repre-
sent the consequences of social position in facilitating acquisition of
the standard human capital characteristics. (Loury 1977, 176)

Loury was unquestionably right in this assessment, and certainly some-
one growing up in East New York, Brooklyn, or the South Side of Chica-
go is not starting from the same position as someone growing up in
Greenwich, CT, or Glencoe, IL. This is stating the obvious. But Loury
needed to make the argument because this apparently self-evident state-
ment of reality was clearly not self-evident to human capital theorists
who, following Becker (1957, 1964), had come to dominate labor theo-
ries in American economics. Human capital formation, instead of being
understood as the inherently social process that it is—for example, no
one goes to school in isolation from the context in which that school is
located, administered, or funded—had come to be almost completely
about individual achievement or lack of it.

A concurrently developed theory of social capital came from French
sociologist Pierre Bourdieu (1985),2 who is relatively underused in the
current literature on social capital in community development. This is
unfortunate because his is probably the most theoretically useful and
sophisticated attempt to deal with the issue. Bourdieu’s (1985) use of
the term social capital is an explicit attempt to understand the produc-
tion of classes and class divisions. Social capital, while being constituted
by social networks and relationships, is never disconnected from capital.
Capital, for Bourdieu (1985), is simultaneously both economic and a set
of power relations that constitute a variety of realms and social inter-
actions normally thought of as noneconomic. Two key components of his
work have been lost in current discussions of social capital. First, the
production, and reproduction, of capital is a process that is inherently
about power. In fact, Bourdieu’s (1985) conception of capital is such that
he almost conceives of capital and power as synonymous. Second, since
his interest is in the social production of classes, he distinguishes be-
tween the social networks that an individual is embedded in, and out of
which social capital precipitates (or emerges), and the outcomes of those
social relationships. That is, social networks should not simply be equat-
ed to the products of those social relationships, for doing so would ren-

The Myth of Social Capital in Community Development 783

2 Similarly, this section draws heavily on the work of Fine (1998, 1999, 2001).

der invisible social networks that might be very dense but nonetheless
unable to generate resources because of lack of access.

Despite these earlier efforts, the person who brought social capital into
the mainstream in the American social sciences was clearly James
Coleman (1988), who argued:

Social capital is defined by its function. It is not a single entity but
a variety of different entities, with two elements in common: they
all consist of some aspect of social structures, and they facilitate cer-
tain actions of actors…within the structure. Like other forms of cap-
ital, social capital is productive, making possible the achievement of
certain ends that in its absence would not be possible. Like physical
and human capital, social capital is not completely fungible but may
be specific to certain activities. A given form of social capital that is
valuable in facilitating certain actions may be useless or even harm-
ful for others. Unlike other forms of capital, social capital inheres in
the structure of relations between actors and among actors. (S98)

With this rather “fuzzy” definition (Markusen 1999; Portes 1998), Cole-
man (1988) then defines different sets of actions, outcomes, and rela-
tionships as social capital. Social capital for him is inherently functional,
and social capital is whatever allows people or institutions to act. Social
capital is therefore not a mechanism, a thing, or an outcome, but simul-
taneously any or all of them. Portes (1998) sees this as a vital step in
the evolution and proliferation of the idea of social capital and states:
“Coleman himself started that proliferation by including under the term
some of the mechanisms that generated social capital; the consequences
of its possession; and the ‘appropriable’ social organization that provided
the context for both sources and effects to materialize” (5). Finally, social
capital, for Coleman (1988), is normatively and morally neutral. That is,
it is neither desirable nor undesirable; it simply allows actions to take
place by providing the needed resources.

Putnam and the proliferation of social capital theory

Although Coleman’s 1988 work brought social capital into use in the
social sciences, the principal source of the idea for community develop-
ment practitioners and researchers is Robert Putnam (1993a, 1993b,
1995, 1996, 2000). With his work, social capital is thoroughly redefined
and becomes extremely influential in development studies, both in the
United States (Gittell and Vidal 1998; Lang and Hornburg 1998; Miller
1997; Moore Lappe and Du Bois 1997; Schulgasser 1999; Servon 1999;
Temkin and Rohe 1998; Wallis 1998; Wallis, Crocker, and Schechter
1998; Wilson 1997) and internationally. In fact, to many people in the
World Bank, social capital has become “the missing link” in global eco-
nomic development (Harriss and de Renzio 1997). Describing the impact
of Putnam’s social capital on community development, Chupp bluntly

784 James DeFilippis

states, “In the debate over poor neighborhoods and the ills of society as
a whole, social capital has become something of a wonder drug” (1999,
2). Further, Putnam’s redefinition of social capital is almost as dramatic
as the widespread impact of his argument, and it therefore requires
considerable discussion here. This article argues that with Putnam’s re-
definition, social capital ceases to be a useful framework for local or
community economic development.

There are several key transitions that occur when Putnam first uses
the term social capital in Making Democracy Work (1993a), his book
on Italian politics. And while he has expanded and developed his views
since then, he has not fundamentally altered them. First, social capital
is transformed from something realized by individuals to something
possessed (or not possessed) by either individuals or groups of people
in regions, communities, cities, countries, or continents. Second, it is
conflated with civil society, or more accurately, with a particular neo-
Tocquevillean view of civil society. Thus, voluntary, nongovernment asso-
ciations, based on trust, become the institutions through which social
capital is generated. Third, it becomes primarily a normatively good
thing and is given credit for (a) promoting good, democratic government
and (b) generating and sustaining economic growth and development.
Finally, when Putnam brings this framework to the American context,
he does so by making the argument that social capital and civil society
are declining in the United States and have been since the mid-1960s
(1993b, 1995, 1996, 2000) and that this trend portends long-term eco-
nomic and political trouble. These issues will be addressed in turn,
before turning to the problems with them and their applications in
community development efforts.

Loury (1977), Bourdieu (1985), and Coleman (1988) all argued that social
capital is not embodied in any particular person, but rather is embedded
in people’s social relationships. At the same time, however, they also
stated that social capital was realized by individuals. Putnam, converse-
ly, has argued that social capital is a resource that individuals or groups
of people possess or fail to possess (Portes 1998; Portes and Landolt
1996). At the outset of his first article on the issue, he states, “Working
together is easier in a community blessed with a substantial stock of
social capital” (Putnam 1993b, 36). Communities, not people, possess
“stocks” of social capital. He has since made this transition from the in-
dividual to the larger group more explicit and states, “Social capital can
thus be simultaneously a ‘private good’ and a ‘public good’ ” (Putnam
2000, 20). What is important to note is that despite his emphasis on
social networks and his moving social capital from the scale of the in-
dividual to the scale of the group, Putnam measures social capital with
a form of methodological individualism (Skocpol 1996). In his research
on social capital in the United States, Putnam (1995, 1996, 2000) uses
social survey data to observe the level of social involvement of individ-
uals and then simply aggregates up from there to whatever scale is

The Myth of Social Capital in Community Development 785

being observed. While this might seem a trivial observation, it is, as
will be demonstrated later, key to his, and his followers’, understanding
of “community.”

Coleman’s (1988) definition, by its lack of clarity, left the door open for
a variety of sources of social capital, and Putnam uses that vagueness
to seize on trust-based voluntary associations (one of the several exam-
ples Coleman offers), and his understanding of them as the constituents
of civil society, as the key source of social capital for communities, re-
gions, and so on. Putnam argues that “social capital refers to the norms
and networks of civil society that lubricate cooperative action among
both citizens and their institutions” (1998, v; emphasis in the original).
Social capital and civil society therefore become conflated, and the two
are almost synonymous. This transition has dramatic implications for
the political and theoretical understandings of social capital.

This view of social capital and civil society, unlike Coleman’s (1988),
Loury’s (1977), and Bourdieu’s (1985), is one in which they are largely
assumed to be a normatively good thing. While Putnam certainly rec-
ognizes that there are potentially “negative” forms of social capital, the
overwhelming balance of his work is about its benefits. And he argues
that they are, in fact, necessary for the functioning of both a responsive
democratic government and the economic growth and well-being of
places. He states:

An impressive and growing body of research suggests that civic con-
nections help make us healthy, wealthy and wise. Living without
social capital is not easy, whether one is a villager in southern Italy
or a poor person in the American inner city or a well-heeled entre-
preneur in a high-tech industrial district. (Putnam 2000, 287)

This understanding of civil society and social capital has its roots in
Putnam’s reading of Alexis de Tocqueville’s (1835) view of civil society
and democracy, and it is therefore necessary to take a moment to dis-
cuss this perspective. De Tocqueville visited the United States in the
1830s and believed that one of the defining components of Democracy
in America (1835) was the propensity of Americans to create and join
voluntary associations that were in the domains of neither the state
nor the market. Putnam acknowledges his debt to de Tocqueville and
states, “Recently, American social scientists of a neo-Tocquevillean bent
have unearthed a wide range of empirical evidence that the quality of
public life and the performance of social institutions are indeed power-
fully influenced by norms and networks of civic engagement” (1995, 66).
His reading of de Tocqueville strongly suggests that networks of trust
and voluntary associations are “win-win” sets of relationships in which
everyone involved benefits. This is evident in his basic definition of the
idea. He states, “Social capital refers to connections among individuals—
social networks and the norms of reciprocity and trustworthiness that
arise from them. In that sense social capital is closely related to what

786 James DeFilippis

some have called ‘civic virtue’ ” (Putnam 2000, 19). Voluntary associa-
tions, therefore, are not confrontational encounters based on vested in-
terests, but rather “features of social life—networks, norms, and trust—
that enable participants to come together to pursue shared objectives”
(Putnam 1996, 34; emphasis added). Bowling leagues, PTAs, Elks Clubs,
church groups, and trade unions (Putnam 1995) are therefore theoreti-
cally, politically, and morally comparable. Even though he examines
them individually in his recent book (Putnam 2000), they all perform
very similar functions.

But, the benefits of social capital and civil society extend beyond simply
promoting and supporting democratic institutions of government to
generating and sustaining economic growth. Putnam argues, “Studies
of the rapidly growing economies of East Asia almost always emphasize
the importance of dense social networks, so that these economies are
sometimes said to represent a new brand of ‘network capitalism’” (1993a,
38). At his boldest (referring to the Italian case), he states, “These com-
munities did not become civic simply because they were rich. The his-
torical record suggests precisely the opposite: They have become rich
because they were civic.…Development economists take note: civics
matters” (1993a, 37). And most recently he states, “Where trust and
social networks flourish, individuals, firms, neighborhoods and even
nations prosper” (Putnam 2000, 319). It is this understanding of social
capital—that it is central to the economic development of communities
and regions and nations—which has inspired its rapid incorporation
into the community economic development literature in the United
States and the underdeveloped world.

Putnam became famous, however, not simply as a neo-Tocquevillean,
but as someone who documented the decline in civil society and social
capital in the United States. His thesis has been much discussed, so it
need not be dealt with in any detail here. Briefly, he has argued (Putnam
1995, 1996, 2000) that the United States has witnessed a withdrawal
from civil society and a decline in social capital. He argues that the de-
cline of social capital is a generational process in which people who were
born in the 1910s and 1920s were (and are) more civicly engaged than
their counterparts who were born from the 1930s on. He accordingly
dates this withdrawal as having begun in the early to mid-1960s.

Putnam’s followers in community development3

Putnam and his arguments have rapidly become central to the research
and practice of community development in the United States. One of
the striking things about this explosion of research and practice around
his view of social capital and civil society is how it has largely ignored

The Myth of Social Capital in Community Development 787

3 The phrase “Putnam’s followers” is borrowed from Gittell and Vidal (1998).

an enormous volume of research and literature by academics (Edwards
and Foley 1997, 1998; Fine 1998, 1999, 2000; Foley and Edwards 1997,
1998; Galston 1996; Portes 1998; Portes and Landolt 1996; Schudson
1996; Skocpol 1996), people in the popular press (Lemann 1996; Pollitt
1996), and activists (Bowles 1999; Durlauf 1999) who have criticized
almost every component of these arguments. Instead, much work in
community development is broadly accepting of Putnam’s arguments
about the importance of social capital, understood as voluntary associ-
ations and civic trust, in the promotion of economic growth and prosper-
ity. In fact, to some researchers, Putnam’s views have become almost
axiomatic, and in the first sentence in her article on social capital Wil-
son unambiguously states: “Social capital creates local economic pros-
perity” (1997, 745). In their introduction to a special issue of Housing
Policy Debate devoted solely to social capital, Lang and Hornburg (1998)
reiterate Putnam’s arguments and state:

Political scientist Robert Putnam expanded and ultimately popular-
ized the concept of social capital. Putnam originally applied the idea
to a study of Italian regional governments. He showed that the key
element underlying the difference between Tuscany’s successful re-
gional government and Sicily’s failed one was the degree of “civic en-
gagement.”…Putnam also argued that social capital is connected to
economic development. Tuscany’s high level of social capital elevates
its standard of living. It provides the region a social environment in
which productive cooperation in all spheres of civic life is possible.
Thus, social capital promotes economic growth. (3; emphasis added)

Similarly, when the Urban Affairs Association held its annual conference
in 1999, it was titled “The Social Reconstruction of the City: Social Cap-
ital and Community Building.” This is certainly not to suggest that
everyone at the meetings accepted Putnam’s arguments, but rather to
observe that his work provided the very framework and context for dis-
cussions. Foundations have similarly incorporated Putnam’s arguments
into their work, and both the Local Initiatives Support Corporation
(LISC) and the Mott Foundation have made the construction of social
capital a central component of their antipoverty and community devel-
opment frameworks. (See Gittell and Vidal [1998] and Wallis, Crocker,
and Schechter [1998] respectively, for thorough discussions of these two
funding initiatives.) In the case of LISC, this has yielded a perspective
on community development organizing that stresses “nonconfrontation-
al” methods, and an incorporation of Michael Eichler’s framework of
“consensus organizing” (Gittell and Vidal 1998, 2). Given that social cap-
ital is being understood as both a set of win-win relationships based on
mutual interest and a promoter of economic prosperity and development,
this is a logical way for community organizers and community develop-
ment practitioners to operate. Thus, Putnam’s view of social capital and
voluntary civic associations is being played out in the streets of Ameri-
can cities. The problem with all of this is that social capital, as Putnam

788 James DeFilippis

has defined and operationalized it, does not necessarily promote com-
munity economic development (or, for that matter, democratic govern-
ment).

The problems with Putnam and his followers

Returning to the way Putnam transformed the idea of social capital, I
will now present the theoretical and empirical flaws in his analysis and
argue that if we are to use the notion of social capital in community
development we would be much better served by returning to how it
was understood by Loury (1977) or Bourdieu (1985). I will go through
Putnam’s transformations of social capital in the same order that they
were presented.

Individuals, communities, and power

First, Putnam defines social capital as something that is possessed, or
not possessed, by individuals, communities, cities, nations, etc. He and
his followers then measure its existence by simply taking individual
attributes and aggregating up to the scale being measured. There are
two problems with this argument and its associated methodology. First,
places are not things. A community cannot possess anything. An institu-
tion or an individual can possess something, but a community cannot.
Instead, communities are products of complicated sets of social, politi-
cal, cultural, and economic relationships (DeFilippis 1999; Massey 1994).
Communities are outcomes, not actors. They are, however, outcomes
that affect and constrain future possibilities. Communities unquestion-
ably matter, but they are not actors that exhibit any form of agency. This
might seem like a semantic argument, but this first problem leads to
the second one. That is, no place (a community, a region, or whatever) is
solely a function of the internal attributes of the people living and work-
ing there. If communities are outcomes, they are not simply outcomes
of the characteristics of those within them, they are also outcomes of a
complex set of power-laden relationships—both internally, within the
communities, and externally, between actors in the communities and the
rest of the world. Citibank (for instance) and its lending practices, state
governments and their education financing policies, and communities
in other countries with soon-to-be emigrants are all very real examples
of how America’s urban communities are products of a whole host of
relations that extend geographically well beyond the place of the com-
munity. These relations are often contentious (school funding issues is a
classic example) and are always imbued with issues of power. Only by
ignoring these vitally important, power-laden connections can we as-
sume that communities are the products of the attributes of the individ-
uals who live and work in them. Similarly, only by ignoring these con-

The Myth of Social Capital in Community Development 789

nections can we assume that we can move from the level of the individ-
ual to the level of community (or city, or region) or that individual gains
and profits are the same as group, or community, gains and profits.

Putnam does try to get at this reality with his concept of “bridging
capital” (1995, 1996, 2000), which has been generally accepted within
the community development work that has followed him. But once we
accept the complexity of the internal and external relationships that
produce a community, we clearly need something more than bridging
capital as the means to economic development. For instance, individuals
in exurban gated communities of Orange County, CA, and indeed in
much of the rest of the country are largely devoid of bridging capital (at
the community level). As Putnam himself states in his brief discussion
of gated communities, “Not only are canvassing politicians and Girl
Scouts selling cookies excluded from exclusive communities, but the af-
fluent residents themselves also appear to have a surprisingly low rate
of civic engagement and neighborliness even within their boundaries”
(2000, 210). The importance of this example is that not only are these
communities disconnected, but they are also usually exceedingly
wealthy. The relationships that produce gated communities are based
on the protection of their affluence through their class- and race-based
social and geographic isolation from much, if not most, of the metropol-
itan areas around them. It is not connections that partially produce and
reproduce their wealth, but exactly the opposite: isolation. Connections,
or “bridges” do not, of themselves, make the people in any place rich or
poor. The important question is, Who controls the terms of any relation-
ships or connections (or lack of connections)? “Bridging capital” is really
needed only if a community’s residents are poor and therefore on the
losing end of a set of power relations. What needs to change are those
power relations, not the level of connections.

Social capital and civil society

The second transition that Putnam makes is to confuse social capital
with a particular neo-Tocquevillean reading of civil society. This transi-
tion has two important implications for community development prac-
tice. First, this reading of civil society assumes that social capital and
civil society are almost always good things that enable people to act to-
ward their shared interests and goals, based on the trust, norms, and
values that develop through their associations. But this is, at best, a
highly selective reading of civil society. Putnam bases his understand-
ing of civil society on the popular simplification of the views de Tocque-
ville expressed in 1835 in Democracy in America. But de Tocqueville’s
view of civil society is both much more complex than Putnam and his
followers acknowledge, and further, it is but one in a very long, and high-
ly contested, history of debate about civil society in Western thought. As
Foley and Edwards correctly observe:

790 James DeFilippis

Tocqueville argues that America’s associational life springs from
the twin social and political conditions of the new nation—and
those conditions are, in his eyes and those of his intended audi-
ence, inherently problematic. The social condition, the relatively
egalitarian character of American society, plays an explicit role in
Tocqueville’s account of the genesis of American associationism. The
political freedoms Americans enjoy play a generally supporting role,
but an essential one. American egalitarianism poses serious prob-
lems for public life to de Tocqueville’s mind…a general leveling
promotes mediocrity and conformism.…Associations arise to fill
these deficiencies. (1997, 554)

De Tocqueville’s voluntary associations arose as win-win situations pre-
cisely because the interests of the people involved were shared. De Toc-
queville visited the United States before the emergence of industrial
capitalism and the classes it created. Also, there is little doubt that if
slaves had been allowed to participate in such associations (which they
clearly were not), then the image of voluntary associations would be a
very different one indeed. Putnam’s view is possible only if you erase
the very real material interests that divide us (and even then, it is still
questionable) and create a vision of civil society as solely constituted by
people and groups with mutual interests. That is why Putnam lumps
trade unions together with PTAs and church groups and views them as
comparable (1993b, 1995, 1996). If he had included local Chambers of
Commerce with local unions, the implausibility of his argument would
have been even clearer. This understanding of voluntary associations
as win-win relationships also allows him to ignore the power relations
that play such an important role in intergroup relations. Simply put,
certain social networks are in greater positions of power than others,
and they can therefore yield much more substantial returns to their
members when those networks are engaged in social or political conflict.
Given that people in low-income areas are marginalized in the Ameri-
can political economy, this is a substantial omission—and limiting fac-
tor—in the potential uses of Putnam’s social capital framework in com-
munity organizing and development.

The second important aspect of conflating social capital with civil society
is that it divorces social capital from capital itself. But for social capital
to have any meaning, it must remain connected to the production and
reproduction of capital in society. This is striking because it is the role
of social capital in community economic development that should be of
the greatest importance to community development practitioners. Com-
munity development is about many things, but central to them must be
the economic security and progress of people in low-income communities
and the economic development of the communities themselves. But given
Putnam’s separation of social capital from economics, it is not surpris-
ing that the economic impact of Putnam’s social capital is so difficult to
observe and measure. This is because it might not even exist.

The Myth of Social Capital in Community Development 791

Social capital and economic growth

Putnam argues that social capital and civil society (comprised of volun-
tary associations) promote economic growth (1993a, 1993b, 1995, 1996,
1998, 2000). But there is little theoretical or empirical support for this
assertion. His own examples, aside from Italy, which is beyond the scope
of this article (his interpretation of Italian politics and economics has
been called into question by other specialists on Italy; see Goldberg
[1996], Harriss and de Renzio [1997], Sabetti [1996], and Tarrow [1996]
for summaries of these criticisms), betray the problems in his own argu-
ment. Putnam uses the examples of immigrant enclaves in American
cities, the “network capitalism” of East and Southeast Asia, and the “ero-
sion of social capital” (Putnam 1993b, 39) in our inner cities as examples
that social capital generates economic growth (or, inversely, that the
lack of social capital arrests economic growth). The first two of these
will be addressed now, and the third shortly.

First, Putnam is certainly right that social ties based on trust and
networks among immigrants have helped them prosper in the United
States. That has been a feature of the immigrant experience for quite
some time. But again, because he views communities as coherent
wholes, internally defined and detached from other sets of communities,
he fails to see the impact of these networks in any larger context. Cole-
man’s (1988) often cited example, which Putnam and his followers draw
on, is that of the diamond industry in New York and how market trans-
actions involving large quantities of jewels are facilitated by the social
networks of trust within the Jewish community that controls the indus-
try. Aside from the complete denial of the exploitation that takes place
within ethnic enclave economies (Waldinger 1986), the problem with
this, and every other enclave like it, is that it completely closes off the
market, and access to the market, to anyone who is not part of the
ethnic group creating the enclave. A brilliant, hard-working, innovative
Irish Catholic immigrant (for instance) who wanted to enter the dia-
mond trade in New York City would have an exceptionally difficult time
doing so. Or to move from the hypothetical to the real, as a result of
large flows of capital into the real estate market in New York, Harlem
has been experiencing substantial development in recent years. This
should be a good thing and beneficial to black contractors and workers
in the community. The reality, however, is that the construction industry
in New York is controlled by an immigrant enclave (in this case Italians),
and so the contracting firms and their employees in Harlem have been
largely excluded from the dollars and jobs that this investment has
brought (Siegal 2000).

The response to this example could be that Harlem contractors simply
need to be better connected or have more substantial stocks of “bridging
capital,” but that would miss the point, which is this: If social capital
as sets of networks means anything, it means that some people will be

792 James DeFilippis

connected and others will not. Simply put, if there is one job, and every-
one is connected to the same networks and realizes the same benefits
of social capital, then you cease to have the kinds of networks that Put-
nam and Coleman are talking about. Instead you have the pure market
of Adam Smith’s theorizations. If everyone is connected, then everyone
by definition would lose the benefits of those connections because they
would no longer gain capital from them (in this case, the job). Putnam
observes, “It is no accident that one of the pervasive strategems of ambi-
tious yuppies is ‘networking’ ” (1993b, 38). But what he fails to realize
is that yuppies network precisely to get ahead of everyone else. If they
shared the fruits of their networking with others, they would cease to
be ambitious and become charitable instead. They would, in fact, not
only be acting charitably, but acting against their own self-interest. This
is one of the primary reasons why it is simply untenable to move from
the level of the individual to the level of community in issues of econom-
ics. For social capital to make sense as a concept in a market economy,
then networks, formal or informal, must operate in the competitive
realm of market relations. And while the individuals in such a network
might share common interests that allow them to act as a network,
these networks, because of the competitive nature of capitalism, cannot
be extended to everyone in society. Max Weber, the influential sociologist
and political economist, wrote at length in 1925 on the role of social
networks in economics in The Theory of Social and Economic Organi-
zation and is instructive on this point. He stated:

[A relationship] is especially likely to be closed, for rational reasons,
in the following type of situation: a social relationship may provide
the parties to it with opportunities for satisfaction of various inter-
ests, whether the satisfactions be spiritual or material.…If the par-
ticipants expect the admission of others will lead to an improvement
of their situation…their interest will be in keeping the relationship
open. If, on the other hand, their expectations are of improving their
position by monopolistic tactics, their interest is in a closed relation-
ship. (Weber 1993 edition, 139–40)

If the social capital in question is a network that helps people find
employment (or get into the right prep school, or whatever), it would
clearly be in the interest of those realizing and appropriating the social
capital (the job or place in the school) to keep the network as closed as
possible. This is precisely what the ethnic enclave economies have dem-
onstrated. To have any value as a term, social capital must retain a
connection to economic capital, and it must therefore be premised on
the ability of certain people to realize it at the expense of others. While
economics is not a zero-sum game, it is also not simply a set of win-win
relationships.

But the economic shortcomings of social capital extend beyond its nec-
essary exclusions and into the realm of economic unsustainability.
Putnam consistently celebrates in his articles the emergence of “network

The Myth of Social Capital in Community Development 793

capitalism” in East and Southeast Asia and argues that these countries
demonstrate the validity of his point that networks of trust and mutual
interest generate economic growth (1993b, 1995, 1996, 1998). The prob-
lem with this example is that by the middle of 1997, the East Asian and
Southeast Asian economies had collapsed, and by the end of 1997, much
of the economic world had decided that the cause of the collapse was
“crony capitalism” (“How Far Is Down?” 1997; “A Lorry-Load of Trouble
in Asia” 1997; “Asia and the Abyss” 1997).

In short, the networks of trust and mutual cooperation in Asia that Put-
nam is so supportive of were taken to their logical conclusion of irra-
tional economic actions inspired by economic decisions that were made
with a logic other than economics at heart. This is probably why in his
recent book Putnam (2000) no longer points to this example. And this
is precisely why Adam Smith in his 1776 Wealth of Nations argued so
strongly against the kinds of social networks among economic actors
that Putnam and his followers now celebrate. Smith argued that such
relationships were akin to monopolization and would necessarily gen-
erate a group whose “interest is, in this respect, directly opposite to that
of the great body of the people” (1993 edition, 307). In fact, he argued
that too much trust between economic actors was a recipe for economy-
stifling cartels and monopolizations—a prediction that seems to have
been borne out by the experience in Asia. Similar concerns were again
voiced by Weber in 1925, but his criticisms went beyond simple exclu-
sions and monopolizations to stress that such trust-based networks
further distort and hamper growth within the economy by inviting free-
riders from within the relationships not to work as hard as they might,
or have to, if they were not connected.

But, the biggest flaw in Putnam’s argument comes not from East Asia
or the theories of political economists, but from the empirical realities
of American life. Three components of Putnam’s arguments with regard
to social capital and economic prosperity are important here: first, that
social capital promotes economic growth; second, that social capital is
declining in the United States and has been since the early to mid-
1960s; third, that inner-city areas lack social capital, which is one of the
principal reasons they are poor. I will address these arguments in turn.

In perhaps the most thorough cross-country empirical examination of
the relationship between social capital and national economic wealth—
one that Putnam cites as supporting his argument—Knack and Keefer
(1997) find a statistically significant positive relationship between lev-
els of trust in a society and rates of economic growth. This is not sur-
prising, since trust at the level of the society should limit the costs of
economic transactions within any given society. Important for this dis-
cussion, however, they also found that “associational activity is not cor-
related with economic performance” (Knack and Keefer 1997, 1252)

794 James DeFilippis

and that “promoting horizontal associations through encouraging the
formation of and participation in groups may be counterproductive,
according to our findings” (Knack and Keefer 1997, 1284).

Within the United States, the evidence is not any more convincing. In
his recent book, Putnam (2000) constructs a “Comprehensive Social
Capital Index” in which each state is ranked along a spectrum of very
high to very low in terms of social capital. Of the 10 states he ranks as
having the highest social capital in the country, only 3 have a per capita
income higher than the per capita income for the entire country (U.S.
Bureau of the Census 2000). Also, the mean per capita income of those
10 states is only 93.9 percent of the country’s per capita income. Clearly,
there are many explanations for why these states are significantly poor-
er than the nation as a whole, and it is definitely not the argument here
that social capital hinders economic prosperity. But if social capital is
important in promoting economic prosperity, then surely the data would
look different from this.

The decline of social capital?

Moving on to the second argument, that social capital is declining in the
United States, the question asked here is, What segments of the popu-
lation is this most true for? After sifting the evidence, Putnam unam-
biguously states, “The central fact is that by virtually all measures of
civic disengagement and all measures of socioeconomic status, the trends
are very similar at all levels” (2000, 194). But if this is true, the question
becomes, Why are the American elites, who have gone through 35 years
of civic disengagement, doing so incredibly well financially? Where is
the economic impact of their disengagement? Affluent and professional
Americans have enjoyed a virtually unprecedented period of prolonged
prosperity, and the current gap in wealth between rich and poor is
greater than it has been since before the Great Depression. Putnam’s
theory just does not make sense in, let alone explain, this reality.

Aside from the incredible growth in the wealth of rich people and the
stagnation in the wealth of poor people—even though both groups have
had their social capital decline by comparable amounts—Putnam’s argu-
ments still run afoul of basic empirical realities in the United States.
That is, social capital is supposed to have declined for 35 years. Where
is the economic impact? It has been 35 years. Given how rapidly invest-
ment decisions are made and economic transformations take place (35
years ago almost nobody had heard of deindustrialization or Silicon
Valley), that is certainly more than enough time for us to have seen an
impact of this declining stock of social capital. Can any evidence of a
relative economic decline of the United States be found? Can people
convincingly argue that the past 20 years have been poor ones for the

The Myth of Social Capital in Community Development 795

American economy overall? Ultimately, if Putnam is right about the
decline in social capital, then he is wrong about the role of social capital
in economic development.

But moving from American society in general to community develop-
ment in particular, Putnam’s second assertion is as follows:

Although most poor Americans do not reside in the inner city, there
is something qualitatively different about the social and economic
isolation experienced by the chronically poor blacks and Latinos who
do. Joblessness, inadequate education, and poor health clearly trun-
cate the opportunities of ghetto residents. Yet so do profound defi-
ciencies in social capital. (1993b, 39)

But do inner cities lack social capital in the sense that Putnam means?
The answer to this question is somewhat mixed and is not as easily
answered as is often assumed. There seems to be a perception in Amer-
ican policy circles and white popular culture that inner-city, nonwhite
neighborhoods are bereft of values, norms, morals, trust, and relation-
ships. This perception is usually justified with a passing reference to
the work of Wilson (1987), but it is a very particular segment of his work
that is being referenced and a very narrow reading of him and his much
more substantial project. This has been as true in the debate about
social capital as in many other debates about public policy, despite the
fact that there is only limited justification for this view. As Portney and
Berry put it:

The debate about social capital and civic engagement largely con-
centrates on White, middle-class America. Virtually none of the de-
bate and, as far as we can find, no empirical analysis considers
whether poor people, people of minority racial or ethnic status, and
people in inner cities have also experienced the trends in civic
engagement. (1997, 633)

When it comes to trust-based relations, ethnographic research (Ander-
son 1999; Stack 1974; Sullivan 1997; Wood 1997) strongly suggests that
these are present in inner cities. Anderson describes some of these trust-
based relations in his most recent book and terms them “the irregular
economy.” He observes:

The irregular economy may be characterized as a barter system,
which works by an exchange of favors. For example, an individual
will repair a neighbor’s car on the weekend, or help paint someone’s
steps, or perform a plumbing job, or style someone’s hair, but take
no money for it; rather, the person will wait to be paid back with a
favor in the future. (Anderson 1999, 318)

It is interesting to note that for Anderson, these trust-based “irregular
economy” activities exist because of the failure of the people and the com-
munity to function properly economically. It is unclear, at best, whether

796 James DeFilippis

such informal trust-based bartering would coexist with economic devel-
opment or that comparable relationships exist in already wealthy com-
munities. In this sense, there is even the possibility that economic
growth and development might promote the destruction of trust-based
noncommodified relationships, as the communities become more im-
mersed in the commodity relations central to the capitalist economy. But
Anderson’s (1999) ethnographic observations are not isolated, and in
making this point more generally, Portes states, “Sociologists know that
everyday survival in poor urban communities frequently depends on
close interactions with kin and friends in similar situations. The problem
is that such ties seldom reach beyond the inner city” (1998, 13–14). The
problem in inner cities, therefore, is not that there is a lack of trust-
based social networks and mutual support, but rather that these net-
works and support are unable to generate capital. At the same time,
however, aggregate data suggest that residents in inner-city areas do
tend to lack trust in either society at large or in people they do not know
(Putnam does a good job of compiling these data [2000]). But these ag-
gregate data do not contradict the ethnographic data indicating that
trust in already existing social networks is present in inner cities.

Regarding the existence of community-level organizations, inner-city
areas contain large numbers of these as well. Specifically with regard to
community development, the number of community development corpo-
rations (CDCs) in American inner cities has actually exploded in the
past 30 years, beginning, ironically, shortly after the time when Putnam
marks the start of the decline of civic engagement. While the number
of CDCs in the late 1960s and early 1970s (most created by the Office
of Economic Opportunity) was measured in the dozens, by 1999 there
were over 3,600 of them nationwide (National Congress for Community
Economic Development 1999). Although it can be argued that many of
these CDCs were not the product of grassroots action at the community
level and were instead created from without, this does not diminish
their existence as nongovernment, not-for-profit organizations located
within low-income communities. The more important problem is that
the ability of most of these community-based organizations to generate
long-term economic growth for their communities has been rather lim-
ited (Lenz 1988; Stoecker 1997). And while the reasons are complex
and require a much more thorough discussion than is possible here, it is
also clear from this experience that simply creating community-based
organizations in inner-city neighborhoods does not, by itself, generate
economic prosperity or even economic security for the residents.

In perhaps the most comprehensive quantitative effort to measure the
impact of Putnam’s social capital on the long-term stability of urban
neighborhoods, Temkin and Rohe (1998) found that “the extent to
which neighborhood residents volunteer in neighborhood organizations
or other groups did not have a significant effect on neighborhood stabil-
ity” (85). This is a striking conclusion, but it does not prevent them from

The Myth of Social Capital in Community Development 797

observing that “neighborhoods with higher levels of social capital…are
more likely to remain stable over time” (Temkin and Rohe 1998, 84).
But if one reads closely, it becomes clear that the dependent variables
and independent variables are measuring the same thing, so it is no
wonder that Temkin and Rohe have found a statistical correlation. They
state, “Both loyalty and attachment to neighborhood are higher in neigh-
borhoods that remain stable over time. Similarly, neighborhoods where
a higher proportion of residents believe they live in a good place tend to
remain stable” (Temkin and Rohe 1998, 84). This is a fair conclusion,
but it seems to say very little.

Even more striking is that the demonstration project for LISC’s non-
confrontational consensus organizing in the Monangahela Valley in
Pittsburgh was viewed a success by LISC and by Gittell and Vidal (1998)
because within 10 years it had (1) created 17 new CDCs, (2) sustained
resident volunteer commitment, and (3) garnered increased support from
the metropolitan area’s larger community. Gittell and Vidal then state,
“These commitments are particularly impressive given the limited
physical and economic improvement in the valley to date” (1998, 3–4).
But if there has been little economic improvement over the course of a
decade, then why is the demonstration considered a success that LISC
and other foundations should replicate? Surely social capital is meant
to be a means to the end of economic security and development, not an
end in and of itself.

Inner cities, therefore, do lack social capital, but not the social capital
that Putnam is talking about—which does exist, albeit rather uneven-
ly—but social capital as Bourdieu (1985) and Loury (1977) used the
term. Part of the problem is that because of Coleman’s (1988) definition,
we have confused the level of social networks with their ability to gen-
erate capital. We therefore render invisible social networks unable to
generate capital. But the question remains, How can we rectify the cur-
rently inequitable distribution of social capital (in Bourdieu’s [1985]
and Loury’s [1977] sense) in American society? In attempting to answer
this question, I will now turn to the policy implications of the discussion
thus far.

Toward a new understanding of social capital
and community development

Social capital must be reconnected to economic capital for the term to
have any meaning. Otherwise, we are not talking about capital at all.
Loury’s original use of the concept (1977) was part of his effort to dem-
onstrate that the idea of equal opportunity was an impossibility. He was
right. When his definition is combined with Bourdieu’s (1985) under-
standing of capital as essentially about power, we can begin to approach

798 James DeFilippis

policy and organizing efforts designed to rectify, or at least, mitigate, the
inequities in access to this form of capital. We need to create social net-
works that allow individuals to realize capital, while simultaneously
allowing these networks to realize the power needed to attract and con-
trol that capital (for the benefit of those in the networks). That is, while
we need to create social networks to allow individuals to realize capital,
those networks must ensure that the groups of people involved retain
some control over the capital. Only in doing this can individual gains
and interests be assumed to be synonymous with group gains and in-
terests. Fortunately, such networks, and the organizations that are their
focal points, already exist within the community development move-
ment and need not be created from scratch. They are, however, rather
limited in number and are small, often peripheral components of the
much broader and more diverse movement. The utility of social capital
is that it provides a framework for supporting and prioritizing these
efforts over other parts of the community development field.

Community land trusts (CLTs) are a particularly useful way to use a
community organization both to have the power to control investment
capital and to allow individuals to realize capital (in the form of home
equity) (Davis 1991; Krinsky and Hovde 1996; Soifer 1990). In a CLT,
the community group owns and controls the land in trust, and all land
use decisions are made by the organization. Residents in a CLT own
their own housing units (unless they are in a mutual housing associa-
tion [MHA] or cooperative, which is not normally the case) and there-
fore obtain the equity they build up in their units through their invest-
ments and improvements. If residents choose to leave, the land trust
has the right of first refusal, and the resale of their unit is limited, so
that it remains affordable (to the benefit of the community), but the
individual is able to realize his or her own investments (to the individ-
ual’s benefit).

In an MHA, the association owns the land and the units, but individual
residents are able to realize some equity because of the interest gained
on the initial deposit required for residency (which is usually between
$1,000 and $2,500 and is often borrowed from the association and paid
back slowly over time) (Krinsky and Hovde 1996; Neighborhood Rein-
vestment Corporation 1995; Peterman and Young 1991). Residents in an
MHA are also much more interconnected than residents in a CLT, most
CDCs, or public housing because of the substantial number of involun-
tary social interactions that come from the work and governance com-
ponents of residency. MHAs are also a bit more mixed income than many
other kinds of affordable housing, and thus the networks through which
employment might be found (for instance) cut across class lines. Simi-
larly, in a limited-equity housing cooperative, residents buy shares and
are thus able to accumulate equity. At the same time, however, the coop-
erative has the right of first refusal when a resident chooses to move,

The Myth of Social Capital in Community Development 799

and the resale price is strictly limited, so as to maintain the units’
affordability for the community as a whole (Leavitt and Saegert 1990;
Stone 1993).

Beyond the realm of housing, microenterprise lending circles are an ex-
cellent example of how organizations can act as focal points for social
networks to come together and have the power to make lending deci-
sions, and to allow individual members to realize capital from those net-
works (McLenighan and Pogge 1991; Servon 1999). In a microenterprise
lending program, borrowers tend to operate in borrowing circles that re-
place the more mainstream evaluations of creditworthiness with both
peer pressure and character-based lending. Loan decisions are made by
members of the borrowing circles, and the loans are used by individual
members to create and expand forms of self-employment and microbusi-
nesses. Individuals are thus able to realize capital through social net-
works, but the power to control capital is realized by the networks
themselves.

Finally, in community development credit unions (CDCUs), individuals
are able to use their membership to gain access to capital they would
likely otherwise not be able to get (DeFilippis 2000; Tholin and Pogge
1991; Williams 1997), while enabling the CDCU, and often its sponsor-
ing organization, to have more control and power over the flow of invest-
ment capital into the community. In the context of social capital, how-
ever, CDCUs do have a drawback in that the level of social interaction
between members, and therefore the social networking that exists be-
tween them, is somewhat limited. This is particularly true for the larger,
often more established CDCUs. Thus the CDCU, as the focal point for
the social networks, often subsumes those networks, and interactions
are between individual members and the CDCU.

Conclusion: Social capital, power, and the
implications for policy and organizing

Despite the provocative title of this article, I am not arguing here that
social capital does not matter in community development. Rather, I argue
that with the privileging of Putnam’s interpretations of social capital,
the term has lost its potential utility for the community development
movement. In Putnam’s understanding of the term, social capital
becomes divorced from capital (in the literal, economic sense), stripped
of power relations, and imbued with the assumption that social net-
works are win-win relationships and that individual gains, interests,
and profits are synonymous with group gains, interests, and profits.

Putnam’s framework is fundamentally economically flawed—which is
not surprising given that he separates social capital from economic
capital—and it enjoys limited support from either theories of political

800 James DeFilippis

economy or the empirical realities of the United States. Also, Putnam’s
understanding, with its lack of power and conflict, has led to a misguided
embrace of Eichler’s consensus organizing and nonconfrontational orga-
nizing (Gittell and Vidal 1998). But this begs the following question:
Why would those who benefit from the current structures that produce
and distribute social capital willingly turn over their privileged access
to it? We would not expect rich people to willingly turn over their mutual
fund portfolios or, less hypothetically, embrace poor and nonwhite stu-
dents in their schools without a confrontation. Why should we expect
that this form of capital would somehow be different from the others?
People who realize capital through their networks of social capital do
so precisely because others are excluded.

Rather than assuming that social networks and relationships are win-
win endeavors and that low-income people and areas are socially dis-
connected, we need to construct social networks that are truly win-win
relationships for people in low-income areas, while building on already
existing social networks and relationships. And we need to do so in ways
that allow those networks to realize greater control and power over the
flows of capital that play such an important role in shaping and pro-
ducing American cities. Inner-city neighborhoods have social networks
and trust between members of those networks, and they possess many
nongovernment, community-based organizations. What they lack is
power and the capital that partially constitutes that power. They are
not likely to realize either without confrontation or within a Putnam-
inspired framework of community development.

Author

James DeFilippis is Lecturer in the Department of Geography at King’s College, London.

References

Anderson, Elijah. 1999. Code of the Street: Decency, Violence and the Moral Life of the
Inner City. New York: Norton.

Asia and the Abyss. 1997. Economist, December 20, pp. 17–18.

Becker, Gary. 1957. The Economics of Discrimination. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.

Becker, Gary. 1964. Human Capital. New York: National Bureau of Economic
Research.

Bourdieu, Pierre. 1985. The Forms of Capital. In Handbook of Theory and Research for
the Sociology of Education, ed. John Richardson, pp. 241–58. New York: Greenwood.

Bowles, Samuel. 1999. “Social Capital” and Community Governance. Focus: Newsletter
of the Institute for Research on Poverty 20(3):6–10.

The Myth of Social Capital in Community Development 801

Chupp, Mark. 1999. Investing in People through Place: The Role of Social Capital in
Transforming Neighborhoods. A Literature Review of Social Capital and Neighborhood
Transformation. Cleveland: Cleveland State University, Levine College of Urban Affairs.

Coleman, James. 1988. Social Capital in the Creation of Human Capital. American
Journal of Sociology 94(supplement):S95–S120.

Davis, John. 1991. Contested Ground: Collective Action and the Urban Neighborhood.
Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

DeFilippis, James. 1999. Alternatives to the “New Urban Politics”: Finding Locality
and Autonomy in Local Economic Development. Political Geography 18:972–90.

DeFilippis, James. 2000. Alternatives to “Corrective Capitalism”: Collective Ownership
and the Possibility of Local Autonomy in Community Development. Ph.D. diss. Rutgers
University, Department of Geography.

de Tocqueville, Alexis. 1835. Democracy in America. Reprint 1998. Ed. Patrick Ranshaw,
trans. Henry Reeve. Garden City, NY: Doubleday.

Durlauf, Steven. 1999. The Case “against” Social Capital. Focus: Newsletter of the
Institute for Research on Poverty 20(3):1–5.

Edwards, Bob, and Michael Foley. 1997. Social Capital and the Political Economy of
Our Discontent. American Behavioral Scientist 40(5):669–78.

Edwards, Bob, and Michael Foley. 1998. Civil Society and Social Capital beyond Putnam.
American Behavioral Scientist 42(1):124–39.

Fine, Ben. 1998. From Bourdieu to Becker: Economics Confronts the Social Sciences.
International Papers in Political Economy 5(3):1–43.

Fine, Ben. 1999. The Developmental State Is Dead—Long Live Social Capital? Develop-
ment and Change 30:1–19.

Fine, Ben. 2001. Social Capital Versus Social Theory: Political Economy and Social
Science at the Turn of the Millenium. London: Routledge.

Foley, Michael, and Bob Edwards. 1997. Escape from Politics? Social Theory and the
Social Capital Debate. American Behavioral Scientist 40(5):550–61.

Foley, Michael, and Bob Edwards. 1998. Beyond Tocqueville: Civil Society and Social
Capital in Comparative Perspective. American Behavioral Scientist 42(1):5–20.

Friedan, Betty. 1963. The Feminine Mystique. Reprint 1984. New York: Dell.

Galston, William. 1996. Won’t You Be My Neighbor? American Prospect, May–June,
pp. 16–18.

Gittell, Ross, and Avis Vidal. 1998. Community Organizing: Building Social Capital as
a Development Strategy. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage.

Goldberg, Ellis. 1996. Thinking about How Democracy Works. Politics and Society
24(1):7–18.

Hamilton, William. 1999. How Suburban Design Is Failing Teen-Agers. New York Times,
May 6, p. F1.

802 James DeFilippis

Hanson, Chris. 1996. The Cohousing Handbook: Building a Place for Community. Point
Roberts, WA: Hartley and Marks.

Harriss, John, and Paolo de Renzio. 1997. “Missing Link” or Analytically Missing? The
Concept of Social Capital. Journal of International Development 9(7):919–37.

How Far Is Down? 1997. Economist, November 15, pp. 25–27.

Jackson, Kenneth. 1985. Crabgrass Frontier: The Suburbanization of the United States.
New York: Oxford University Press.

Katz, Peter. 1994. The New Urbanism: Toward an Architecture of Community. New
York: McGraw-Hill.

Knack, Ruth Eckdish. 1996. Once upon a Town. Planning 62(3):10–13.

Knack, Stephen, and Philip Keefer. 1997. Does Social Capital Have an Economic Payoff?
A Cross-Country Investigation. Quarterly Journal of Economics 112(4):1251–88.

Krinsky, John, and Sarah Hovde. 1996. Balancing Acts: The Experience of Mutual
Housing Associations and Community Land Trusts in Urban Neighborhoods. New York:
Community Service Society.

Lang, Robert, and Steven Hornburg. 1998. What Is Social Capital and Why Is It
Important to Public Policy? Housing Policy Debate 9(1):1–16.

Langdon, Philip. 1994. A Better Place to Live: Reshaping the American Suburb. Amherst,
MA: University of Massachusetts Press.

Leavitt, Jacqueline, and Susan Saegert. 1990. From Abandonment to Hope: Community-
Households in Harlem. New York: Columbia University Press.

Lemann, Nicholas. 1996. Kicking in Groups. Atlantic Monthly, April, pp. 22–26.

Lenz, Thomas. 1988. Neighborhood Development: Issues and Models. Social Policy,
spring, pp. 24–30.

A Lorry-Load of Trouble in Asia. 1997. Economist, December 6, pp. 93–94.

Loury, Glenn. 1977. A Dynamic Theory of Racial Income Differences. In Women,
Minorities, and Employment Discrimination, ed. Phyllis Wallace and Annette LaMond,
pp. 153–88. Lexington, MA: Heath.

Markusen, Ann. 1999. Fuzzy Concepts, Scanty Evidence, Policy Distance: The Case for
Rigour and Policy Relevance in Critical Regional Studies. Regional Studies 33(9):869–84.

Massey, Doreen. 1994. Space, Place, and Gender. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press.

McCamant, Kathryn, and Charles Durrett. 1988. Cohousing: A Contemporary Approach
to Housing Ourselves. Berkeley, CA: Habitat.

McLenighan, Valjean, and Jean Pogge. 1991. The Business of Self-Sufficiency: Micro-
credit Programs in the United States. Chicago: Woodstock Institute.

Miller, Roberta. 1997. Healthy Boston and Social Capital: Application, Dynamics, and
Limitations. National Civic Review 86(2):157–66.

The Myth of Social Capital in Community Development 803

Moore Lappe, Francis, and Paul Martin Du Bois. 1997. Building Social Capital without
Looking Backward. National Civic Review 86(2):119–28.

Muschamp, Herbert. 1996. Can the New Urbanism Find Room for the Old? New York
Times, June 2, pp. 27.

National Congress for Community Economic Development. 1999. Member Information.
Washington, DC.

Neighborhood Reinvestment Corporation. 1995. Mutual Housing Associations. Boston.

Peterman, William, and Mary Anne Young. 1991. Alternatives to Conventional Public
Housing Management. Chicago: University of Illinois, Natalie P. Voorhees Center for
Neighborhood and Community Improvement.

Pollitt, Katha. 1996. For Whom the Ball Rolls. Nation, April 15, p. 9.

Portes, Alejandro. 1998. Social Capital: Its Origins and Applications in Modern Sociology.
Annual Review of Sociology 24:1–24.

Portes, Alejandro, and Patricia Landolt. 1996. The Downside of Social Capital. American
Prospect, May–June, pp. 18–21, 94.

Portney, Kent, and Jeffrey Berry. 1997. Mobilizing Minority Communities: Social Capital
and Participation in Urban Neighborhoods. American Behavioral Scientist 40(5):632–44.

Putnam, Robert. 1993a. Making Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Putnam, Robert. 1993b. The Prosperous Community: Social Capital and Public Life.
American Prospect, spring, pp. 35–42.

Putnam, Robert. 1995. Bowling Alone: America’s Declining Social Capital. Journal of
Democracy 6:65–78.

Putnam, Robert. 1996. The Strange Disappearance of Civic America. American Prospect,
winter, pp. 34–48.

Putnam, Robert. 1998. Foreword. Housing Policy Debate 9(1):v–viii.

Putnam, Robert. 2000. Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American Community.
New York: Simon and Schuster.

Sabetti, Filippo. 1996. Path Dependency and Civic Culture: Some Lessons from Italy
about Interpreting Social Experiments. Politics and Society 24(1):19–44.

Schiff, Stephen. 1999. Littleton, Then and Now. New York Times, April 22, pp. A31.

Schudson, Michael. 1996. What if Civic Life Didn’t Die? American Prospect, March–April,
pp. 17–20.

Schulgasser, Daniel. 1999. Making Something out of Nothing: Social Capital
Development in Newark, New Jersey’s, Enterprise Community. National Civic Review
88(4):341–50.

Servon, Lisa. 1999. Bootstrap Capital: Microenterprises and the American Poor. Wash-
ington, DC: Brookings Institution.

804 James DeFilippis

Siegal, Nina. 2000. Fighting for Jobs on Their Own Turf. New York Times, April 23, pp. 4.

Skocpol, Theda. 1996. Unravelling from Above. American Prospect, March–April, pp.
20–25.

Smith, Adam. 1776. Wealth of Nations. Reprint 1993. New York: Oxford University
Press.

Soifer, Steve. 1990. The Burlington Community Land Trust: A Socialist Approach to
Affordable Housing? Journal of Urban Affairs 12(3):237–52.

Stack, Carol. 1974. All Our Kin. New York: Harper & Row.

Stoecker, Randy. 1997. The CDC Model of Urban Redevelopment: A Critique and an
Alternative. Journal of Urban Affairs 19(1):1–22.

Stone, Michael. 1993. Shelter Poverty: New Ideas on Housing Affordability. Philadelphia:
Temple University Press.

Sullivan, Lisa. 1997. Hip-Hop Nation: The Undeveloped Social Capital of Black Urban
America. National Civic Review 86(3):235–43.

Talen, Emily. 1999. Sense of Community and Neighbourhood Form: An Assessment of
the Social Doctrine of New Urbanism. Urban Studies 36(8):1361–75.

Tarrow, Sidney. 1996. Making Social Science Work across Space and Time: A Critical
Reflection on Robert Putnam’s Making Democracy Work. American Political Science
Review 90(2):389–97.

Temkin, Kenneth, and William Rohe. 1998. Social Capital and Neighborhood Stability:
An Empirical Investigation. Housing Policy Debate 9(1):61–88.

Tholin, Kathryn, and Jean Pogge. 1991. Banking Services for the Poor: Community
Development Credit Unions. Chicago: Woodstock Institute.

U.S. Bureau of the Census. 2000. Statistical Abstract of the United States. Washington,
DC.

Waldinger, Roger. 1986. Through the Eye of the Needle: Immigrants and Enterprise in
New York’s Garment Trades. New York: New York University Press.

Wallis, Allan. 1998. Social Capital and Community Building: Part Two. National Civic
Review 87(4):317–36.

Wallis, Allan, Jarle Crocker, and Bill Schechter. 1998. Social Capital and Community
Building: Part One. National Civic Review 87(3):253–71.

Weber, Max. 1925. The Theory of Social and Economic Organization. Reprint 1993. Ed.
Talcott Parsons. New York: Free Press.

Williams, Marva. 1997. Credit to the Community: The Role of CDCUs in Community
Development. Chicago: Woodstock Institute.

Wills, Garry. 2000. Putnam’s America. American Prospect 11(16). World Wide Web page
(accessed October 3, 2001).

Wilson, Patricia. 1997. Building Social Capital: A Learning Agenda for the Twenty-

The Myth of Social Capital in Community Development 805

First Century. Urban Studies 34(5–6):745–60.

Wilson, William Julius. 1987. The Truly Disadvantaged. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.

Wood, Richard. 1997. Social Capital and Popular Culture: God Meets Politics in the
Inner City. American Behavioral Scientist 40(5):595–605.

Wood, Robert. 1958. Suburbia: Its People and Their Politics. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

806 James DeFilippis

Expert paper writers are just a few clicks away

Place an order in 3 easy steps. Takes less than 5 mins.

Calculate the price of your order

You will get a personal manager and a discount.
We'll send you the first draft for approval by at
Total price:
$0.00